From: quasi on 11 Aug 2010 03:44 William Elliot recently posted this question: If a commutative ring is such that all elements except 1 are zero divisors, must it be a Boolean ring? Remark: Actually, William Elliot asked the same question several years ago, and soon after that, I posted a construction showing that such a ring need not be Boolean. In other words, I specified a construction for a commutative ring such that not all elements are idempotent, but for which every element except 1 is a zero divisor. Was my construction correct? Beats me -- I hardly remember the details. It was years ago, but as I recall, no one made objections at the time. On the other hand, no on affirmed it either. Below is a repost of my construction. First, some terminology ... For this discussion, the term ring will mean commutative ring with 1, and with 1 != 0. Call a ring unit-trivial if 1 is the only unit. Note that Z is not unit-trivial since -1 is a unit distinct from 1. It's easy to show that a unit-trivial ring must have characteristic 2. Some simple examples of unit-trivial rings: the field Z_2 the polynomial ring Z_2[x] However it's not true that every ring of characteristic 2 is unit-trivial. For example the field of rational functions Z_2(x) has characteristic 2 but is clearly not unit-trivial. By an embedding R->R' we will mean an injective homomorphism of the ring R into the ring R'. It's automatic that an embedding R->R' takes idempotents to indempotents, non-idempotents to non-idempotents, units to units, and zero divisors to zero divisors. However it's not necessarily true that an embedding R->R' takes nonunits to nonunits or non-zero-divisors to non-zero-divisors. In fact, part of our strategy is to define embeddings which force non-zero-divisors to become zero divisors while simultaneously not creating any new units. The construction ... Let R be any unit-trivial ring. Let X={x_M | M is a maximal ideal of R} be a set of independent indeterminates. Consider the polynomial ring R[X]. Note -- by R[X] we mean the ring of multivariable polynomials in the set of indeterminates from X with coefficients in R. Let J be the ideal of R[X] generated by the union of the sets M*x_M for all maximal ideals M of R together with the union of the sets {x_M1*x_M2} for all pairs of distinct maximal ideals M1,M2 of R. Let R'=R[X]/J. I'll make 3 claims about R', deferring the proofs until the end so as not to distract from the main argument. (1): The composite map R->R[X]->R[X]/J gives an embedding of R->R'. (2): All elements of R except 1 become zero divisors in R'. (3) R' is unit-trivial. Thus, assuming the validity of the 3 claims, we get the following theorem ... Theorem 1: Any ring unit-trivial ring R can be embedded in a unit-trivial ring R' such that all elements of R except 1 become zero divisors in R'. We can use direct limits to strengthen theorem 1 ... Theorem 2: Any unit-trivial ring R can be embedded in a ring T such that all elements of T except 1 are zero divisors. proof of theorem 2: Starting with R_0=R, and applying theorem 1, we can construct an infinite chain of embeddings R_0->R_1->R_2->... such that for all n, R_n is unit-trivial and such that all elements of R_n except 1 are zero divisors in R_(n+1). Let T be the direct limit of the system R_0->R_1->R_2->... Any element of T can be obtained from an element of R_n for some n, but since R_(n+1) also embeds in T, it follows that all elements of T except 1 are zero divisors. Next, by applying theorem 2 to an appropriate ring R, we can get the example we seek ... Let R be any unit-trivial ring such that not every element of R is idempotent. For example, we could let R be the univariate polynomial ring Z_2[x]. Applying theorem 2, we can embed R into a ring T such that all elements of T except 1 are zero divisors. But R has non-idempotent elements hence, since R->T is an embedding, any non-idempotent element of R maps to a non-idempotent element of T. Therefore the ring T is a commutative ring such that all elements except 1 are zero divisors, but not every element is idempotent. This completes the construction. It remains to prove the 3 claims. Be warned -- the proofs are routine but somewhat tedious. We need the following preliminary results. claim (A): If p is in J, each monomial of p is in J. This is automatic since J is generated by monomials. claim (B): Any univariate monomial in J has the form r*(x_M)^k where r is in M. Suppose r*(x_M)^k is in J. Thus, suppose r*(x_M)^k is a weighted combination of the generators of J with weights from R[X]. Then we have an equation of the form equation (1): r*(x_M)^k = weighted combination of the generators of J with weights from R[X] In equation 1, substitute 0 for all variables x_N except x_M to get equation (2): r*(x_M)^k = weighted combination of generators of J of the form a*x_M, with weights from R[x_M], and where a is in M. Hence the polynomial on the right side of equation 2, viewed as an element of R[x_M], has all coefficients in M, and on the left hand side, the coefficient of (x_M)^k is r. It follows that r is in M, as claimed. claim (1) : The composite map R->R[X]->R[X]/J gives an embedding of R->R'. That the composite map is an embedding follows from the fact that the ideal J in R[x], when contracted back to R, yields the 0 ideal. To see that the contraction of J back to R is 0, simply note that all elements of J have 0 constant term. claim (2): All elements of R except 1 become zero divisors in R'. Let r be an element of R, r=/=1. Then r is in some maximal ideal M of R. But then in R', r*x_M=0. But by claim (B), x_M is not in J, hence x_M is not 0 in R', and therefore r is a zero-divisor, as claimed. claim (3): R' is unit-trivial. Suppose instead there exists f',g' in R' such that f'*g'=1 and f',g'=/=1. Choose f,g in R[X], reduced mod J, such that f maps to f' and g maps to g'. By reduced mod J, we mean no monomial term of either f or g is in J. Let a_0 be the constant term of f, and b_0 be the constant term of g. Then f*g=1 mod J implies a0*b0=1 mod J. Since J contracts to 0 in R, it follows that a0*b0=1. Since R is unit-trivial, it follows that a0=1 and b0=1. Thus, we can write f=f1+1, g=g1+1, where f1,g1 have no constant term. Also, since f=/=1, g=/=1, it follows that f1,g1 are both nonzero Since f,g are reduced mod J, each monomial in either f1, g1 is univariate. Let var_f = the set of indeterminates actually present in f, and let var_g = the set of indeterminates actually present in g. Suppose var_f intersect var_g is empty. Then since the product of any 2 distinct indeterminates is in J, f1*g1=0 mod J, hence f*g=(f1+1)*(g1+1)=f1*g1+f1+g1+1=f1+g1+1 mod J. But then f*g=1 mod J implies f1+g1=0 mod J. But f1 and g1 are both nonconstant and reduced mod J. Since they have distinct indeterminates, the can be no cancellation of terms mod J, so f1+g1=0 is impossible. Hence f and g have some common indeterminate, x_M, say. For ease of notation, let x=x_M. Let a_j*x^j be the leading term of f with respect to x, and let b_k*x^k be the leading term of g with respect to x. Since the terms are reduced, we know that a_j and b_k are not in M. Then, the leading term of f*g with respect to x is a_j*b_k*x^(j+k). Since it's the only term of it's kind, no cancellation with another term is possible. But f*g=1 mod J implies f*g-1 is in J, hence by claim (A), all monomials of f*g-1 are in J. Since a_j and b_k are not in M, a_j*b_k is not in M, hence, by claim (B), the term a_j*b_k*x^(j+k) is not in J, so this term survives mod J in f*g as well as in f*g-1, contradiction. This proves claim (3). The proof is now complete. quasi
From: Bill Dubuque on 11 Aug 2010 17:37 quasi <quasi(a)null.set> wrote: > William Elliot recently posted this question: > > If a commutative ring is such that all elements except 1 > are zero divisors, must it be a Boolean ring? > > Remark: > > Actually, William Elliot asked the same question several years ago, > and soon after that, I posted a construction showing that such a ring > need not be Boolean. In other words, I specified a construction for a > commutative ring such that not all elements are idempotent, but for > which every element except 1 is a zero divisor. Was my construction > correct? Beats me -- I hardly remember the details. It was years ago, > but as I recall, no one made objections at the time. On the other > hand, no on affirmed it either. > > Below is a repost of my construction. [...] Cohn showed how to do this long ago. Namely, as a corollary to another result, he shows that any commutative ring with a unit-element 1, which has no invertible elements other than 1, can be embedded in a ring in which every element unequal to 1 is a zerodivisor. See P. M. Cohn. Rings of zero-divisors. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 9 (1958), 909-914 http://www.ams.org/journals/proc/1958-009-06/S0002-9939-1958-0103202-2/S0002-9939-1958-0103202-2.pdf --Bill Dubuque
From: quasi on 11 Aug 2010 19:55 On 11 Aug 2010 17:37:38 -0400, Bill Dubuque <wgd(a)nestle.csail.mit.edu> wrote: >quasi <quasi(a)null.set> wrote: >> William Elliot recently posted this question: >> >> If a commutative ring is such that all elements except 1 >> are zero divisors, must it be a Boolean ring? >> >> Remark: >> >> Actually, William Elliot asked the same question several years ago, >> and soon after that, I posted a construction showing that such a ring >> need not be Boolean. In other words, I specified a construction for a >> commutative ring such that not all elements are idempotent, but for >> which every element except 1 is a zero divisor. Was my construction >> correct? Beats me -- I hardly remember the details. It was years ago, >> but as I recall, no one made objections at the time. On the other >> hand, no on affirmed it either. >> >> Below is a repost of my construction. [...] > >Cohn showed how to do this long ago. Namely, as a corollary to another >result, he shows that any commutative ring with a unit-element 1, >which has no invertible elements other than 1, can be embedded in >a ring in which every element unequal to 1 is a zerodivisor. See > >P. M. Cohn. Rings of zero-divisors. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 9 (1958), 909-914 >http://www.ams.org/journals/proc/1958-009-06/S0002-9939-1958-0103202-2/S0002-9939-1958-0103202-2.pdf Thanks for the link. Interestingly, Cohn's proof looks to be essentially the same as mine, which suggests to me that the underlying proof idea is a natural one. quasi
|
Pages: 1 Prev: Rubi 2 (Rule-based integrator, version 2) Next: x^2 = 4*y^3 + 1 |