From: zuhair on
On Nov 24, 12:55 am, Rupert <rupertmccal...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
> On Nov 23, 10:37 pm, zuhair <zaljo...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
>
>
>
>
>
> > On Nov 22, 9:20 pm, Rupert <rupertmccal...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
>
> > > On Nov 23, 11:37 am, zuhair <zaljo...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
>
> > > > On Nov 22, 7:16 pm, Rupert <rupertmccal...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
>
> > > > > On Nov 23, 10:01 am, zuhair <zaljo...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
>
> > > > > > Hi all,
>
> > > > > > As far as I know, all the definitions of cardinality are limited in a
> > > > > > way or another, lets take them one after the other:
>
> > > > > > 1) Von Neumann's Cardinals:
>
> > > > > > A cardinal is the least of all equinumerous ordinals.
>
> > > > > > 2) Frege-Russell Cardinals:
>
> > > > > > A cardinal is an equivalence class of sets under equivalence relation
> > > > > > "bijection".
>
> > > > > > 3) Scott-Potter Cardinals:
>
> > > > > > A cardinal is a class of all equinumerous sets from a common level.
>
> > > > > > Now lets come to discuss each one of them:
>
> > > > > > 1) Von Neumann's cardinals has the limitation of being dependent on
> > > > > > choice, without choice one cannot know what is the cardinality of
> > > > > > Power(omega) for example.Accordingly in any theory which do not have
> > > > > > the axiom of choice among its axioms most of its sets would be of
> > > > > > indeterminable cardinality, which is a big draw back.
>
> > > > > > 2) Frege-Russell cardinals contradict Z set theory, since their
> > > > > > existence would imply the existence of the set of all sets, which is
> > > > > > in contradiction with Z.
>
> > > > > > However in NBG and MK class theories, we can define
> > > > > > Frege-Russell cardinals, but by then they would be proper classes and
> > > > > > not sets, which is a great draw back, since proper classes cannot be
> > > > > > members of other classes, and they are hard to work with.
>
> > > > > > In NF and related theories, Frege-Russell cardinals are sets, but
> > > > > > these theories generally depend on the concept of stratification
> > > > > > of formulas, which is a complex concept, and even finite
> > > > > > axiomatization of NF and NFU and related theories is a complicated
> > > > > > approach, and at the end it also resort to stratification for most of
> > > > > > its inferences. All that make these cardinals undesirable.
>
> > > > > > 3) Scott-Potter Cardinals: depend on the concept of "level" which
> > > > > > depends on the concept of type (Scott) and the iterative concept
> > > > > > (Potter), both concepts of which are complex and difficult to work
> > > > > > with, besides they are not the basic
> > > > > > concepts we use to compare set sizes.
>
> > > > > > I would like to suggest the following definition:
>
> > > > > > 4) The cardinality of any set x is: The class of all sets
> > > > > > that are equinumerous to x were every member of their transitive
> > > > > > closure is strictly subnumerous to x.
>
> > > > > > So for any set x, any y is a member of the cardinality of x,
> > > > > >  if and only if, y is equinumerous to x and every member of the
> > > > > > transitive closure of y is strictly subnumerous to x.
>
> > > > > > In symbols:
>
> > > > > > Define(cardinality(x)):-
>
> > > > > > z=cardinality(x) <->
> > > > > >  for all y (y e z <->
> > > > > > (y equi-numerous to x &
> > > > > >  for all m (m e Tc(y)->m strictly subnumerous to x)))
>
> > > > > > Were Tc(y) stands for the 'transitive closure of y' defined
> > > > > > in the standard manner.
>
> > > > > > Tc(y)=U{y,Uy,UUy,UUUy,......}
>
> > > > > > We can actually better define these cardinals through defining the
> > > > > > concept of "hereditary sets"
>
> > > > > > Define(hereditary):
> > > > > >  x is hereditary <->
> > > > > >  for all y (y e Tc(x) -> y strictly subnumerous to x)
>
> > > > > > So a cardinal can be defined in the following manner:
>
> > > > > > A Cardinal is an equivalence class of hereditary sets under
> > > > > > equivalence relation "bijection".
>
> > > > > > Or simply
>
> > > > > > A Cardinal is a class of all equinumerous hereditary sets.
>
> > > > > > So cardinality of x would be written shortly as:
>
> > > > > > Cardinality(x) = {y| y is hereditary & y equinumerous to x}
>
> > > > > > Now it can be proven in ZF that those cardinals would be 'sets', so
> > > > > > they are not proper classes! which makes them easy to handle.
>
> > > > > > These cardinals don't require choice.
>
> > > > > > They don't require complex concepts like "stratification,type,
> > > > > > iteration"
>
> > > > > > They simply depend on the basic concept used to compare set sizes,
> > > > > > which is the presence or absence of injections between the compared
> > > > > > sets.
>
> > > > > > To me this definition seems to be simpler, more general, and it works
> > > > > > with or without choice, with or without regularity.
>
> > > > > > So at the end I shall write the definition of cardinal again:
>
> > > > > > A Cardinal is an equivalence class of hereditary sets under
> > > > > > equivalence relation "bijection".
>
> > > > > > x is hereditary <->
> > > > > >  for all y (y e Tc(x) -> y strictly subnumerous to x)
>
> > > > > > Cardinality(x) = {y| y is hereditary & y equinumerous to x}
>
> > > > > > Zuhair
>
> > > > > But the question arises: can you prove in ZF that every set has a
> > > > > cardinality, on this definition? Not quite obvious to me just at the
> > > > > moment...
>
> > > >  Well, to say the truth I am not sure either. But from my prior
> > > > discussions
> > > > I got the impression that working in ZF minus Regularity minus Choice,
> > > > it is provable that:
>
> > > >   for any set there exist a set of exactly all sets that are
> > > > hereditarily strictly sub-numerous to it.
>
> > > That is certainly not a problem in ZFC but I certainly don't see right
> > > now how to do it without regularity or choice. You should look into
> > > that one carefully, I should think.
>
> > The sketch of the proof goes like that:
>
> > First we prove that for every set x there exist a set of exactly all
> > sets that are
> > hereditarily strictly subnumerous to it,lets denote that later set by
> > H_(<x)
>
> > so we have: for every x there exist H_(<x)
>
> >  H_(<x) = {y | y strictly subnumerous to x and
> >                     for all z (z e Tc(y) -> z strictly subnumerous to
> > x)}
>
> > as a theorem of ZF.
>
> Well, 'tis surely a theorem of ZFC, but yeah, why would it be a
> theorem of ZF? Let's get clear about that first.
>
> And you were saying you could do it in ZF-regularity.
>
> But, yeah, I would like to know how you do it in ZF.

That is my personal guess, I don't have a proof of that yet.
By the way can you help me regarding this issue, and post the complete
proof of this theorem in ZFC, I think this would be of great help.

Zuhair
From: Rupert on
On Nov 24, 6:15 pm, zuhair <zaljo...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
> On Nov 24, 12:55 am, Rupert <rupertmccal...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
>
>
>
>
>
> > On Nov 23, 10:37 pm, zuhair <zaljo...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
>
> > > On Nov 22, 9:20 pm, Rupert <rupertmccal...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
>
> > > > On Nov 23, 11:37 am, zuhair <zaljo...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
>
> > > > > On Nov 22, 7:16 pm, Rupert <rupertmccal...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
>
> > > > > > On Nov 23, 10:01 am, zuhair <zaljo...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
>
> > > > > > > Hi all,
>
> > > > > > > As far as I know, all the definitions of cardinality are limited in a
> > > > > > > way or another, lets take them one after the other:
>
> > > > > > > 1) Von Neumann's Cardinals:
>
> > > > > > > A cardinal is the least of all equinumerous ordinals.
>
> > > > > > > 2) Frege-Russell Cardinals:
>
> > > > > > > A cardinal is an equivalence class of sets under equivalence relation
> > > > > > > "bijection".
>
> > > > > > > 3) Scott-Potter Cardinals:
>
> > > > > > > A cardinal is a class of all equinumerous sets from a common level.
>
> > > > > > > Now lets come to discuss each one of them:
>
> > > > > > > 1) Von Neumann's cardinals has the limitation of being dependent on
> > > > > > > choice, without choice one cannot know what is the cardinality of
> > > > > > > Power(omega) for example.Accordingly in any theory which do not have
> > > > > > > the axiom of choice among its axioms most of its sets would be of
> > > > > > > indeterminable cardinality, which is a big draw back.
>
> > > > > > > 2) Frege-Russell cardinals contradict Z set theory, since their
> > > > > > > existence would imply the existence of the set of all sets, which is
> > > > > > > in contradiction with Z.
>
> > > > > > > However in NBG and MK class theories, we can define
> > > > > > > Frege-Russell cardinals, but by then they would be proper classes and
> > > > > > > not sets, which is a great draw back, since proper classes cannot be
> > > > > > > members of other classes, and they are hard to work with.
>
> > > > > > > In NF and related theories, Frege-Russell cardinals are sets, but
> > > > > > > these theories generally depend on the concept of stratification
> > > > > > > of formulas, which is a complex concept, and even finite
> > > > > > > axiomatization of NF and NFU and related theories is a complicated
> > > > > > > approach, and at the end it also resort to stratification for most of
> > > > > > > its inferences. All that make these cardinals undesirable.
>
> > > > > > > 3) Scott-Potter Cardinals: depend on the concept of "level" which
> > > > > > > depends on the concept of type (Scott) and the iterative concept
> > > > > > > (Potter), both concepts of which are complex and difficult to work
> > > > > > > with, besides they are not the basic
> > > > > > > concepts we use to compare set sizes.
>
> > > > > > > I would like to suggest the following definition:
>
> > > > > > > 4) The cardinality of any set x is: The class of all sets
> > > > > > > that are equinumerous to x were every member of their transitive
> > > > > > > closure is strictly subnumerous to x.
>
> > > > > > > So for any set x, any y is a member of the cardinality of x,
> > > > > > >  if and only if, y is equinumerous to x and every member of the
> > > > > > > transitive closure of y is strictly subnumerous to x.
>
> > > > > > > In symbols:
>
> > > > > > > Define(cardinality(x)):-
>
> > > > > > > z=cardinality(x) <->
> > > > > > >  for all y (y e z <->
> > > > > > > (y equi-numerous to x &
> > > > > > >  for all m (m e Tc(y)->m strictly subnumerous to x)))
>
> > > > > > > Were Tc(y) stands for the 'transitive closure of y' defined
> > > > > > > in the standard manner.
>
> > > > > > > Tc(y)=U{y,Uy,UUy,UUUy,......}
>
> > > > > > > We can actually better define these cardinals through defining the
> > > > > > > concept of "hereditary sets"
>
> > > > > > > Define(hereditary):
> > > > > > >  x is hereditary <->
> > > > > > >  for all y (y e Tc(x) -> y strictly subnumerous to x)
>
> > > > > > > So a cardinal can be defined in the following manner:
>
> > > > > > > A Cardinal is an equivalence class of hereditary sets under
> > > > > > > equivalence relation "bijection".
>
> > > > > > > Or simply
>
> > > > > > > A Cardinal is a class of all equinumerous hereditary sets.
>
> > > > > > > So cardinality of x would be written shortly as:
>
> > > > > > > Cardinality(x) = {y| y is hereditary & y equinumerous to x}
>
> > > > > > > Now it can be proven in ZF that those cardinals would be 'sets', so
> > > > > > > they are not proper classes! which makes them easy to handle.
>
> > > > > > > These cardinals don't require choice.
>
> > > > > > > They don't require complex concepts like "stratification,type,
> > > > > > > iteration"
>
> > > > > > > They simply depend on the basic concept used to compare set sizes,
> > > > > > > which is the presence or absence of injections between the compared
> > > > > > > sets.
>
> > > > > > > To me this definition seems to be simpler, more general, and it works
> > > > > > > with or without choice, with or without regularity.
>
> > > > > > > So at the end I shall write the definition of cardinal again:
>
> > > > > > > A Cardinal is an equivalence class of hereditary sets under
> > > > > > > equivalence relation "bijection".
>
> > > > > > > x is hereditary <->
> > > > > > >  for all y (y e Tc(x) -> y strictly subnumerous to x)
>
> > > > > > > Cardinality(x) = {y| y is hereditary & y equinumerous to x}
>
> > > > > > > Zuhair
>
> > > > > > But the question arises: can you prove in ZF that every set has a
> > > > > > cardinality, on this definition? Not quite obvious to me just at the
> > > > > > moment...
>
> > > > >  Well, to say the truth I am not sure either. But from my prior
> > > > > discussions
> > > > > I got the impression that working in ZF minus Regularity minus Choice,
> > > > > it is provable that:
>
> > > > >   for any set there exist a set of exactly all sets that are
> > > > > hereditarily strictly sub-numerous to it.
>
> > > > That is certainly not a problem in ZFC but I certainly don't see right
> > > > now how to do it without regularity or choice. You should look into
> > > > that one carefully, I should think.
>
> > > The sketch of the proof goes like that:
>
> > > First we prove that for every set x there exist a set of exactly all
> > > sets that are
> > > hereditarily strictly subnumerous to it,lets denote that later set by
> > > H_(<x)
>
> > > so we have: for every x there exist H_(<x)
>
> > >  H_(<x) = {y | y strictly subnumerous to x and
> > >                     for all z (z e Tc(y) -> z strictly subnumerous to
> > > x)}
>
> > > as a theorem of ZF.
>
> > Well, 'tis surely a theorem of ZFC, but yeah, why would it be a
> > theorem of ZF? Let's get clear about that first.
>
> > And you were saying you could do it in ZF-regularity.
>
> > But, yeah, I would like to know how you do it in ZF.
>
> That is my personal guess, I don't have a proof of that yet.
> By the way can you help me regarding this issue, and post the complete
> proof of this theorem in ZFC, I think this would be of great help.
>
> Zuhair- Hide quoted text -
>
> - Show quoted text -

If I assume the axiom of choice, then every set can be well-ordered,
and is equipollent to some cardinal kappa, a cardinal being a von
Neumann ordinal not equipollent to any smaller ordinal.

Now let R(0) be the empty set, and for any R(alpha), let R(alpha+1) be
the set of all subsets of R(alpha) of cardinality less than kappa, and
for any limit ordinal beta, let R(beta) be the union of all R(alpha)
for alpha<beta. Iterate this up to R(kappa). In ZF I can prove this is
a set, using transfinite recursion and suchlike, and this is the set
you're after.

Fair enough?

But without the axiom of choice I know longer know that the set can be
well-ordered... and so it is not really clear what sort of transfinite
recursion to use.

Do you get that? Do you want me to explain in more detail?
From: George Greene on
On Nov 24, 12:55 am, Rupert <rupertmccal...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
> But, yeah, I would like to know how you do it in ZF.

You can't do it in ZFC either.
ZFC DOES NOT assign a cardinality (in the usual sense)
to p(w).


From: George Greene on
On Nov 24, 3:23 am, Rupert <rupertmccal...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:

> If I assume the axiom of choice, then every set can be well-ordered,

Right.


> and is equipollent to some cardinal kappa,

WRONG.

Ex[whatever]
does NOT mean that there exists a UNIQUE x such that whatever!
There are MANY DIFFERENT well-orderings of p(w) under ZFC and
they correspond TO DIFFERENT ordinals!

> a cardinal being a von
> Neumann ordinal not equipollent to any smaller ordinal.

ZFC does NOT assign a cardinality to p(w) or any other uncountable set
except maybe the alephs. Under ZFC, beth-1 (=p(w)=p(aleph-0)
=2^beth-0)
"can" take ANY aleph-n (where n is natural) as a cardinality!

Remember, there was that whole conunundrum about
THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS ?!?!?!!?
From: zuhair on
On Nov 24, 10:15 am, George Greene <gree...(a)email.unc.edu> wrote:
> On Nov 24, 12:55 am, Rupert <rupertmccal...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
>
> > But, yeah, I would like to know how you do it in ZF.
>
> You can't do it in ZFC either.
> ZFC DOES NOT assign a cardinality (in the usual sense)
> to p(w).

Dear George Greene, please answer the following questions:

Is the following a theorem of ZFC or not?

For all s Exist x for all y
( y e x <-> (y strictly subnumerous to s and
for all z (z e Tc(y) -> z strictly subnumerous to
s)).

were Tc(y) stands for the transitive closure of y.

in case it is a theorem of ZFC, then is it a theorem of ZF? i.e.
without choice,
and if it is a theorem of ZF, then is it a theorem of ZF minus
regularity?

Simple questions that demand simple answer and proofs of these
answers!

Zuhair