From: Dik T. Winter on
In article <1152189366.413919.218240(a)p79g2000cwp.googlegroups.com> mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de writes:
>
> Dik T. Winter schrieb:
>
> > But the order type of your set of transpositions is w * w.
>
> Sorry, I do not see that. Every sequence of transpositions leaves a
> first, a second, a third element. And there is no element number oo. By
> definiton, that is order-type omega. That is a well-ordered set with
> ordinal number omega.

You have a sequence of transpositions T1, T2, T3, ..., followed by
a sequence of transpositions T1', T2', T3', ..., followed, ..., etc.
That total sequence of transpositions has order type w * w.

> > Moreover,
> > different orderings of the same subset of transpositions will yield
> > different results. In the formula I gave for the diagonal number,
> > calculation of one digit does *not* depend on the calculation of
> > another digit.
>
> And what is the consequence of this?

That the calculation of the digits can be done in parallel?

> > It is Cauchy's theorem that proves that the limit exists, using the
> > epsilon argument.
>
> But Cantor's arguing is that without epsilon.

I do not know Cantor's argument exactly. I think that he implicitly
uses that result. In my formulation it was abundantly clear that I did
use it.

> > > When I stay within the domain of finite numbers.
> >
> > You do not. Or you are re-ordering a subset of the rationals, not all
> > rationals.
>
> Which part do I not re-order?

Sorry, I did misread.

>
> > > If the transpositions are well-ordered, they are indexed by finite
> > > numbers - up to the last one.
> >
> > Wrong. In the first place, there is not necessarily a last transposition,
>
> OK. So let's better say: The transpositions are indexed by finite
> numbers - up to every one.
>
> > and in the second place they are not necessarily indexed by finite numbers.
> > Consider the following (well-ordered) sequence of transpositions (where I
> > use, as you do, index numbers):
> > (1, 2)(3, 4)(5, 6)(7, 8)...(1, 3)(2, 4)(5, 6)(7, 8)...
> > what is the finite index number of the transposition (1, 3)?
>
> I don't know it because the set of transpositions has not the
> order-type omega. But if all the transpositions are countable (which is
> correct without doubt) and if countability means that every member of
> the set (of transpositions) can be enumerated, then (1, 3) has a finite
> number.

It can be indexed by a finite number. Right. But in that case there is
no connection between the index numbers and the ordering.

> But recently you raised the problem that the ordinal number of the set
> of all transpositions is not omega. This is in fact a problem, as your
> above question shows again, because we cannot count up to or even
> beyond the first limit-ordinal number. But I think I can remedy this
> disadvantage in the following way.
>
> Start with transpositions of the indices:
> (1, 2)
> (2, 3)
> (1, 2)
> This orders the set of the first three elements by size. Then order the
> set of the first 4 elements by size.
> (1, 2), (3, 4)
> (2, 3)
> (1, 2)
>
> And so on. After the set of the first n elements has been ordered by
> size, order the set of the first n+1 element by size. At most n-1
> transpositions are required for a set of n elements. Now, the complete
> set of transpositions is of order type omega. And it maintains the
> well-order by index while it achieves well-order by size.

And again, it maintains the well order as long as you remain in the finite
domain. So up to every finite n, you have ordered the first n elements
of the well-ordered list, retaining a finite list. And back again to
problem 1 with this. How do you define that when n grows without bound?
How do you define the "limit"? And if you define that, is that "limit"
also well-ordered? Those are things you have to prove.
--
dik t. winter, cwi, kruislaan 413, 1098 sj amsterdam, nederland, +31205924131
home: bovenover 215, 1025 jn amsterdam, nederland; http://www.cwi.nl/~dik/
From: Dik T. Winter on
In article <1152193390.830398.326300(a)q16g2000cwq.googlegroups.com> mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de writes:
....
> > > Either the diagonal number 0.111... is not distinguished from all
> > > finitely large numbers of the list
> > > 0.
> > > 0.1
> > > 0.11
> > > 0.111
> > > ...
> > > then Cantor's proof fails.

If we assume that that list contains natural numbers in some unary notation
(as I think you do) than:

> > > Or 0.111... is distinguished from all finitely large numbers of the

0.111... is not a natural number in unary notation. So it is inherently
different from all elements of the list.

> "To be different" means for all unary representations of n
> An : 0.111... - n =/= 0

How do you propose to define that subtraction when 0.111... is not a
natural number?

> Every digit can be indexed by a natural number means that there is no
> digit, which is different from all unary representations of natural
> numbers.

Right.

> By construction of 0.111... this means further that every
> digit at position n and all digits at smaller positions can be indexed.
> This means there does not exist any digit which differs from all unary
> representations.
> not forall n: 0.111... - n =/= 0

But that is a wrong conclusion. Let's call 0.111... (as a sequence of
digits) K. And let's define K[i] is the i'th digit of K and An[i] the
i'th digit of An. The following statement is correct:
There is no i such that for all n K[i] != An[i] (1)

> En : 0.111... - n = 0.

And that is wrong, because that means:
There is an n such that for all i K[i] = An[i]. (2)
pray tell us under what logical reasoning you transform (1) to (2).

And to simplify it, take A0 = 0.10, A1 = 0.01, K = 0.11. (1) is
satisfied, (2) is not satisfied.
--
dik t. winter, cwi, kruislaan 413, 1098 sj amsterdam, nederland, +31205924131
home: bovenover 215, 1025 jn amsterdam, nederland; http://www.cwi.nl/~dik/
From: David Hartley on
In message <1152191768.157605.15960(a)b68g2000cwa.googlegroups.com>,
mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de writes
>
>David Hartley schrieb:
>>
>> Infinite processes can be brought to an end if they have a clearly
>> defined limit. You haven't defined what you mean by the limits of the
>> orderings or mappings produced by your process. To make "this result
>> occur unavoidably" you need to give definitions of both limits and show
>> that the limit of the mappings is an order-isomorphism from N to the
>> limit of the orderings. Using the definitions I offered, the sequence of
>> orderings does have a limit, and it is the usual ordering of the
>> positive rationals. The limit of the associated sequence of mappings
>> from N would be an order-isomorphism if it existed but - no surprise -
>> it doesn't.
>
>The limit is clear. The question is why it is not reached.
>>
>> Unless you at least try to define these limits, and to prove the
>> required relationship between them, I see little point in continuing
>> this discussion.
>
>Here is a set of transpositions of order type omega. Therefore we stay
>once and for all in the finite natural numbers.
>Start with transpositions of the indices:
> (1, 2)
> (2, 3)
> (1, 2)
>This orders the set of the first three elements by size. Then order the
>set of the first 4 elements by size.
> (1, 2), (3, 4)
> (2, 3)
> (1, 2)
>
>And so on. After the set of the first n elements has been ordered by
>size order the set of the first n+1 element by size. At most n-1
>transpositions are required for a set of n elements. Now, the complete
>set of transpositions is of order type omega. And it maintains the
>well-order by index while it achieves well-order by size.

Your quoted transpositions don't alter the ordering as you want, but the
intention is clear and that does work. (It is the sequence I suggested a
couple of days ago.) Now let a_n be the first element of the ordering
achieved by rearranging the first n elements of the original order. It
is clearly the minimum of the first n elements. The sequence <a_n> is
thus non-increasing and unbounded below (in the positive rationals). Let
f_n be the mapping from N which indexes the ordering achieved at the nth
stage. You claim this sequence "clearly" has a limit, say f. Given that
f_n(1) = a_n, what is f(1)? And don't say f(1) must be the non-existent
smallest positive rational and so set theory is inconsistent. You need
to prove, within standard set theory, that there *is* a well-defined
limit with the required properties before you can claim a contradiction.

Good-bye.
--
David Hartley
From: Virgil on
In article <1152180620.790783.87220(a)75g2000cwc.googlegroups.com>,
mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:

> Virgil schrieb:
>
>
> >
> > Also, in ZF, ZFC and NBG, any countable union of countable sets can be
> > proved countable, so "mueckenh"'s attempts to claim otherwise must fail.
>
> Feferman and Levy showed that one cannot prove that there is any
> non-denumerable set of real numbers which can be well ordered.

In ZFC and NBG, every set is in theory well-orderable.


> Moreover, they also showed that the statement that the set of all real
> numbers is the union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets cannot be
> refuted.

Where did they show this, and for what system did they show this???
Absent any such reference, I doubt that it is valid in ZFC, and ZFC is
demonstably as consistent as ZF.
From: Christian Clason on
Virgil wrote:
> In article <1152180620.790783.87220(a)75g2000cwc.googlegroups.com>,
> mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:
>> Moreover, they also showed that the statement that the set of all real
>> numbers is the union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets cannot be
>> refuted.
>
> Where did they show this, and for what system did they show this???
> Absent any such reference, I doubt that it is valid in ZFC, and ZFC is
> demonstably as consistent as ZF.

That would be the Feferman-Levy model of ZF (M9 in the treatise of Howard
and Rubin [1], if I recall correctly), where R is indeed a countable union
of countable sets. Of course, not even countable choice can hold in this
model. In this thread, it should be mentioned explicitly that this does not
imply that R is countable, since in this model countable union of countable
sets do not have to be countable.

Best regards,

Christian Clason

[1] Howard, Rubin, Consequences of the Axiom of Choice, AMS Math. Surveys
and Monographs 59, 1998
First  |  Prev  |  Next  |  Last
Pages: 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
Prev: integral problem
Next: Prime numbers