From: Tony Orlow on
cbrown(a)cbrownsystems.com wrote:
> Tony Orlow wrote:
>> cbrown(a)cbrownsystems.com wrote:
>>> Tony Orlow wrote:
>>>> cbrown(a)cbrownsystems.com wrote:
>>>>> Tony Orlow wrote:
>>>>>> Mike Kelly wrote:
>>>>> <snip>
>>>>>
>>>>>>> My question : what do you think is in the vase at noon?
>>>>>>>
>>>>>> A countable infinity of balls.
>>>>>>
>>>>>> This is very simple. Everything that occurs is either an addition of ten
>>>>>> balls or a removal of 1, and occurs a finite amount of time before noon.
>>>>>> At the time of each event, balls remain. At noon, no balls are inserted
>>>>>> or removed.
>>>>> No one disagrees with the above statements.
>>>>>
>>>>>> The vase can only become empty through the removal of balls,
>>>>> Note that this is not identical to saying "the vase can only become
>>>>> empty /at time t/, if there are balls removed /at time t/"; which is
>>>>> what it seems you actually mean.
>>>>>
>>>>> This doesn't follow from (1)..(8), which lack any explicit mention of
>>>>> what "becomes empty" means. However, we can easily make it an
>>>>> assumption:
>>>>>
>>>>> (T1) If, for some time t1 < t0, it is the case that the number of balls
>>>>> in the vase at any time t with t1 <= t < t0 is different than the
>>>>> number of balls at time t0, then balls are removed at time t0, or balls
>>>>> are added at time t0.
>>>>>
>>>>>> so if no balls are removed, the vase cannot become empty at noon. It was
>>>>>> not empty before noon, therefore it is not empty at noon. Nothing can
>>>>>> happen at noon, since that would involve a ball n such that 1/n=0.
>>>>> Now your logical argument is complete, assuming we also accept
>>>>> (1)..(8): If the number of balls at time t = 0, then by (7), (5) and
>>>>> (6), the number of balls changes at time 0; and therefore by (T1),
>>>>> balls are either placed or removed at time 0, implying by (5) and (6)
>>>>> that there is a natural number n such that -1/n = 0; which is absurd.
>>>>> Therefore, by reductio ad absurdum, the number of balls at time 0
>>>>> cannot be 0.
>>>>>
>>>>> However, it does not follow that the number of balls in the vase is
>>>>> therefore any other natural number n, or even infinite, at time 0;
>>>>> because that would /equally/ require that the number of balls changes
>>>>> at time 0, and that in turn requires by (T1) that balls are either
>>>>> added or removed at time 0; and again by (5) or (6) this implies that
>>>>> there is a natural number n with -1/n = 0; which is absurd. So again,
>>>>> we get that any statement of the form "the number of balls at time 0 is
>>>>> (anything") must be false by reductio absurdum.
>>>>>
>>>>> So if we include (T1) as an assumption as well as (1)..(8), it follows
>>>>> logically that the number of balls in the vase at time 0 is not
>>>>> well-defined.
>>>>>
>>>>> Of course, we also find that by (1)..(8) and (T1), it /still/ follows
>>>>> logically that the number of balls in the vase at time t is 0; and this
>>>>> is a problem: we can prove two different and incompatible statements
>>>>> from the same set of assumptions
>>>>>
>>>>> So at least one of the assumptions (1)..(8) and (T1) must be discarded
>>>>> if we are to resolve this. What do you suggest? Which of (1)..(8) do
>>>>> you want discard to maintain (T1)?
>>>>>
>>>>> Cheers - Chas
>>>>>
>>>> This is a very good question, Chas. Thanks. I'll have to think about it,
>>>> and I'm rather tired right now, but at first glance it seems like it
>>>> could be a sound analysis. I've cut and pasted for perusal when I'm
>>>> sharper tomorrow.
>>>>
>>> Here's some of my thoughts:
>>>
>>> When you say "noon doesn't occur"; I think "he doesn't accept (1): by a
>>> time t, we mean a real number t"
>> That doesn't mean t has to be able to assume ALL real numbers. The times
>> in [-1,0) are all real numbers.
>
> And I would say that assuming that by a time t, we mean a real number
> in [-1,0) is a different assumption than (1).
>
>>> When you say "if we always add more balls than we remove, the number of
>>> balls in the vase at time 0 is not 0", I think "he doesn't accept (8):
>>> if the numbers of balls in the vase is not 0, then there is a ball in
>>> the vase."
>> No, I accept that. There is no time after t=-1 where there is no ball in
>> the vase.
>>
>
> I.e., there is a ball in the vase. But then by the argument I
> previously gave, there is then a ball in the vase which is not in the
> vase. Your reference to "unspecified" balls in the vase at noon I
> interpret to be a way of saying that (8) should instead state something
> like "if the number of balls in the vase is not 0, then there may be no
> /specific/ ball in the vase (because there is instead an /unspecific/
> ball in the vase)".
>

Specify the largest natural, and I'll grant you that.

>>> When you say "an infinite number of balls are removed at time 0", I
>>> think "he does not agree with (6) if balls are removed at some time t,
>>> they are removed in accordance with the problem statement: i.e. there
>>> exists some natural number n s.t. n = -1/t and (some other stuff)".
>> I didn't say that exactly. If 0 occurs, then all finite balls are gone,
>> but infinite balls have been inserted such that 1/n=0 for those balls.
>> So, at noon the vase is not empty, even if it occurs in the problem,
>> which it doesn't.
>>
>
> If infinite balls are inserted at some time t = -1/n = 0, then by (5)
> each of them are inserted at time t; and at that time exactly 10 balls
> are inserted. 10 is not infinite.

10 balls per iteration times oo iterations per second is oo (or 10*oo)
balls per second.

>
>>> All these assertions follow a simgle theme: "If I require that my
>>> statemnents be /logically/ consistent, does the given problem make
>>> sense; and if so, what is a reasonable resonse?".
>>>
>>> Cheers - Chas
>>>
>> That there is a contradiction in your conclusion if you assume that all
>> events must occur at some time...
>
> The "occurence" of these events (ball insertions and removals at
> particular times) is described by (1), (5), (6), and (7).

There is the event of becoming empty, i.e., in(t)-out(t)=0. Oh, except,
that never happens.

>
>> ... and that becoming empty is the result of
>> events that happen in the vase.
>
> There is no "becoming" empty described in (1)..(8). There is only
> "being" empty; which is described by (1), (2), (3), and
From: Tony Orlow on
Virgil wrote:
> In article <1161936661.828422.190110(a)e3g2000cwe.googlegroups.com>,
> imaginatorium(a)despammed.com wrote:
>
>> David Marcus wrote:
>>> imaginatorium(a)despammed.com wrote:
>>>> Virgil wrote:
>>>>> In article <45417528$1(a)news2.lightlink.com>,
>>>>> Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
>>>> <snip>
>>>>
>>>>>> For what it's worth, and I know this doesn't add a lot of credibility
>>>>>> to
>>>>>> Ross in your eyes, coming from me, but I think Ross has a genuine
>>>>>> intuition that isn't far off with respect to what's controversial in
>>>>>> modern math. Sure, he gets repetitive and I don't agree with
>>>>>> everything
>>>>>> he says, but his cryptic "Well order the reals", which I actually
>>>>>> haven't seen too much of lately, is a direct reference to his EF
>>>>>> (Equivalence Function, yes?) between the naturals and the reals in
>>>>>> [0,1). The reals viewed as discrete infinitesimals map to the
>>>>>> hypernaturals, anyway, and his EF is a special case of my IFR. So, to
>>>>>> answer your question, I think Ross makes some sense. But, of course,
>>>>>> coming from me, that probably doesn't mean much. :)
>>>>> Coming from TO it damns Ross.
>>>> Even by your standards, Virgil, this is egregiously silly. TO skips the
>>>> basic exposition in Robinson's book, but finds a sentence he likes. So
>>>> this "damns" Robinson's non-standard analysis, does it?
>>> Virgil said "Ross", not "Robinson", I believe.
>> Yes, of course. But Virgil's implication is that "TO says person P is
>> right about something" implies P is wrong. This may, contingently, be
>> true about Ross, but the argument could equally be applied to Robinson,
>> in which case the conclusion is obviously not true.
>
> Since Ross has, by his own posts, shown himself to be as far out of
> touch with reality as TO, TO's approval is only piling Pelion on Ossa.
>
> If TO were to support someone reasonably in touch with mathematical
> reality, I should not have regarded it as a "last straw" situation.

Like Robinson?
From: Tony Orlow on
Virgil wrote:
> In article <1161936661.828422.190110(a)e3g2000cwe.googlegroups.com>,
> imaginatorium(a)despammed.com wrote:
>
>> David Marcus wrote:
>>> imaginatorium(a)despammed.com wrote:
>>>> Virgil wrote:
>>>>> In article <45417528$1(a)news2.lightlink.com>,
>>>>> Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
>>>> <snip>
>>>>
>>>>>> For what it's worth, and I know this doesn't add a lot of credibility
>>>>>> to
>>>>>> Ross in your eyes, coming from me, but I think Ross has a genuine
>>>>>> intuition that isn't far off with respect to what's controversial in
>>>>>> modern math. Sure, he gets repetitive and I don't agree with
>>>>>> everything
>>>>>> he says, but his cryptic "Well order the reals", which I actually
>>>>>> haven't seen too much of lately, is a direct reference to his EF
>>>>>> (Equivalence Function, yes?) between the naturals and the reals in
>>>>>> [0,1). The reals viewed as discrete infinitesimals map to the
>>>>>> hypernaturals, anyway, and his EF is a special case of my IFR. So, to
>>>>>> answer your question, I think Ross makes some sense. But, of course,
>>>>>> coming from me, that probably doesn't mean much. :)
>>>>> Coming from TO it damns Ross.
>>>> Even by your standards, Virgil, this is egregiously silly. TO skips the
>>>> basic exposition in Robinson's book, but finds a sentence he likes. So
>>>> this "damns" Robinson's non-standard analysis, does it?
>>> Virgil said "Ross", not "Robinson", I believe.
>> Yes, of course. But Virgil's implication is that "TO says person P is
>> right about something" implies P is wrong. This may, contingently, be
>> true about Ross, but the argument could equally be applied to Robinson,
>> in which case the conclusion is obviously not true.
>
> Since Ross has, by his own posts, shown himself to be as far out of
> touch with reality as TO, TO's approval is only piling Pelion on Ossa.
>
> If TO were to support someone reasonably in touch with mathematical
> reality, I should not have regarded it as a "last straw" situation.

Like Boole?
From: Tony Orlow on
Virgil wrote:
> In article <4542164c(a)news2.lightlink.com>,
> Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
>
>> Virgil wrote:
>
>>>> Please specify the moment when the vase becomes empty.
>>> It IS empty at noon, but not before. But I do not know what TO means by
>>> "becomes".
>> Become: To assume a state not previously assumed.
>
> Since the vase was empty to start with, it cannot later "become" empty
> after once having been empty, at least according to that definition.
>
>
>>>>> The only relevant question is "According to the rules set up in the
>>>>> problem, is each ball inserted at a time before noon also removed at a
>>>>> time before noon?"
>>>>>
>>>>> An affirmative answer confirms that the vase is empty at noon.
>>>> Not if noon is proscribed the the problem itself, which it is.
>>> How so? I see nothing in the statement of the problem which "proscribes"
>>> noon.
>> Nothing can occur at noon because that implies 1/n=0, false for all
>> natural numbers.
>
> Where in the gedankenexperiment is that required?
>>>>> A negative answer directly violates the conditions of the problem.
>>>>>
>>>>> How does TO answer this question?
>>>>>
>>>>> As usual, he avoids such relevant questions in his dogged pursuit of the
>>>>> irrelevant.
>>>>>
>>>> Noon does not exist in the experiment, or else you have infinitely
>>>> numbered balls.
>
> Two assumptions both at variance with the original gedankenexperiment.
>>> It is specifically mentioned in the experiment as the base time from
>>> which all actions are determined, so that if it does not exist then none
>>> of the actions can occur.
>> No, time begins at -1, such that t(n)=-1/n. n never becomes infinite, so
>> t never becomes 0.
>
> -1 is not a time unless there is a 0 from which to measure it.
>>> If there is no noon then there can be no one minute before noon at which
>>> the first ball is inserted, so the vase is frozen in a state of
>>> emptiness.
>> At t=-1=-1/n, n=1. Are you saying 1 is not a natural number?
>
> I am saying that there are no negative real numbers without a 0 from
> which to to mark them.
>
>> I thought
>> the labels were the most important aspect of this for you. Now you want
>> to ignore them? Huh!
>
> Non sequitur. That I want time to be properly measured does not mean
> require I want to ignore other things.
>>>>>>> Obviously, time is an independent variable in this experiment and the
>>>>>>> insertion or removal or location of balls is a function of time. That's
>>>>>>> what the problem statement says: we have this thing called "time" which
>>>>>>> is a real number and it "goes from" before noon to after noon and, at
>>>>>>> certain specified times, things happen. There are only
>>>>>>> naturally-numbered balls inserted and removed, always before noon.
>>>>>>> Every ball is removed before noon. Therefore, the vase is empty.
>>>>>> No, you have the concept of the independent variable bent. The number of
>>>>>> balls is related to the time by a formula which works in both directions.
>>> Where does the problem say that the numbers on balls being moved
>>> determines the time?
>> Of each event? Where it says that ball n is inserted at time -1/n and
>> removed at time -1/10n. That was a dumb question.
>
> So the moving of the balls is determined by time, not the other way
> around.
>>>>> As time is a continuum and the numbers of balls in the vase is not,
>>>>> there is no way of inverting the realtionship in the way that TO claims.
>>>> Your times are as discontinuous as the number of balls, if no events can
>>>> happen at any other moments than those specified.
>>> That hardly means that there are no other times in between.
>>>
>>> Time is a continuum. Or does TO claim that time is quantized?
>> Where real time is continuous, there is always something happening.
>> That's not the case here.
>
> Sure there is, we are watching continuously!
>
>> The moments during events are a countable
>> subset of the uncountable interval.
>
>
> The moments of change are countable, but in between these moments the
> vase and the balls do not disappear, they still exist, they just don't
> move.
>
>>> So how is the vase be not empty after every ball is removed?
>> There is no "after".
>
> So TO wants to stop the clock? Is his face enough to do it?
>
>
>> You are hiding your largest finite in a moment of
>> infinite processing, but it's leaving a hole in your logic.
>
> TO may want a largest finite in his universe, in which clocks stop for
> no reason, but no one else need have one in theirs.
>
>
>
>
>>>> Like something occurring in time without at least a moment in which it
>>>> occurred.
>>> In the physical world, nothing happens instantaneously. In the
>>> mathematical world, pretty much everything does.
>> Uh, yeah, at specific times. But there is no non-self-contradictory
>> moment in the problem at which the emptying can occur.
>
> A bit of it happens each time a ball is removed, and it is completed
> when every ball has been removed, i.e., at noon.
>
>
> Or does TO's face stop the clock again?
>>> In the mathematical world of the experiment, the balls move in and out
>>> of the vase instantaneously, and must be allowed to do so or the
>>> experiment cannot be performed at all.
>> Of course, each event at a specific time.
>>
>>> So either things can happen instantaneously or the experiment impossible.
>> So what? Happening instantaneously doesn't mean there is no moment in
>> the event. It means there's only one. Without at least occupying one
>> moment, an event does not happen in time. It's like trying to pretend
>> you have a geometric figure that contains no points. The set of times
>> that the vase becomes empty is null.
>
> But there is a noon, if there are any times at all, and at noon the vase
> holds no balls
>>> If TO allows a finite change of number of balls in the vase to occur
>>> instantaneously, what is so difficult about allowing an "infinite"
>>> change in the number of balls to occur instantaneously?
>>>
>>> TO seems to swallow camels and strain at gnats.
>>>
>> There's nothing difficult about that. I agreed that, without removing
>> balls, one gets an uncountable rate of increase at t=0. The problem is
>> that there is no time when it can become empty in the original
>> expe
From: Tony Orlow on
Virgil wrote:
> In article <45421735(a)news2.lightlink.com>,
> Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
>
>> Virgil wrote:
>
>>> In order to have emptiness at noon, all removals must take place no
>>> later than noon, which they are forced to do by the rules of the problem.
>> That means either before noon, or at noon. No balls are removed at noon.
>> Balls remain at every time before noon. You're busted.
>
> Except that every ball inserted before noon has been removed before
> noon according to the specifications of the gedankenexperiment.
>
> So it is TO who is busted for violating the rules of the
> gedankenexperiment.

At least you're not drenching my face with pepper spray. But, then
again, I'm not the one who squealed like a piggy. :)

Chuckles with blood splatters,

Tony