From: zuhair on 1 Jan 2010 04:37 Hi all, In the last one month I've posted many topics on cardinality. This one is also another trial to define cardinality in ZF, i.e. without Choice. First from T. Jeck's paper, it appears that his proof can be generalized to every well orderable set x. So for every well order-able set x, there exist the set of all sets hereditarily subnumerous to x. This is a theorem of ZF. Now this time the main idea of the trial is to associate a unique ordinal with each set in ZF such that all sets equinumerous to each other have a corresponding unique ordinal. So for example lets take any set x, then all sets equinumerous to x would be associated with the same ordinal d(x), now every y that are strictly subnumerous to x would be associated with an ordinal d(y) that is also strictly subnumerous to d(x), same thing applies every set z that is strictly supernumerous to x would be associated with an ordinal d(z) that is strictly supernumerous to d(x). Next step we define for every x, the set of all sets hereditarily subnumerous to d(x) (i.e. the set of all sets that are subnumerous (injective) to d(x) were every member of their transitive closures is also subnumerous to d(x) ) Lets denote this set as H(d(x)) Then we define cardinality as: Cardinality (x) is the class of d(x) and of all subsets of H(d(x)) that are equinumerous to x. The point is how to define d(x). This is a trial: Define(d(x)): A=d(x) <-> for all y ( y e A <-> Exist u,z( u strictly subnumerous to x & z=d(u) & & y is ordinal & y equinumerous to d (u))). This is a trick really, Now we start with x=0 i.e. x is the empty set. we'll see that d(0) = 0, because there do not exist any set u that is strictly subnumerous to 0 so d(0)=0. Now d(x) were x is singleton would be 1 i.e. {0} So for every finite set x, d(x) would be the ordinal that is equinumerous to x, i.e. the Von Neumann cardinal of x. Also for every Countably infinite set x, d(x) would be Omega. However for Aleph_1 , d(x) = Aleph_1 itself. Actually we can conclude that for every ordinal x, d(x) is the Von Neumann Cardinal of x. Now lets take Power(omega) and lets assume it is incomparable to any of the uncountable ordinals. Now d(power(omega))=Aleph_1 d(power(power(omega)))=Aleph_2 etc.... so we managed to define d(x) for every set x. Of course it is easy to prove that d(x) is not empty for every set x in ZF. So now we come to our Cardinal here. Lets take the Cardinality of Power(omega) and lets assume that power omega is not comparable to any of the uncountable ordinals. Now we have H(Aleph_1) as a set in ZF. So the cardinality of power(omega) is the class having Aleph_1 as a member and also having all subsets of H(Aleph_1) that are equinumerous to Power(omega) as members. Now The cardinality of Aleph_1 would be the class of all subsets of H (Aleph_1) that are equinumerous to Aleph_1. Clearly they are not the same cardinality, since all proper subsets of aleph_1 that are equinumerous to Aleph_1 would be members of the Cardinality of Aleph_1, but not of the Cardinality of Power(omega)). Now from the other hand, two sets that are equinumerous, it is obvious that they will have the same cardinality, because the will have the same d(x), and the rest of the sets in their cardinal are equinumerous to each of them. so they will have the same cardinal. two sets that are strictly non equinumerous will also have different cardinals also since their members would not be equinumerous. so: (1)Card(x)=Card(y) iff x and y have the same members(Extensionality). (2)Card(x) > Card (y) iff [(every member of Card(x) is strictly supernumerous to every member of Card (y)) and (every subset of d(x) that is equinumerous to d(x) is a member of Card(x) iff every subset of d(y) that is equinumerous to d(y) is a member of Card (y)) ]. (3)Card(x) < Card(y) <-> Card(y) > Card(x) (4)Card(x) incomparable with Card(y) iff non of the above. Although very complex definition but I think it works. Of course this definition requires Regularity, so it works in ZF, it doesn't require choice. However I have the guess, that this definition can be modified to exclude Regularity also. Zuhair
From: zuhair on 1 Jan 2010 05:08 On Jan 1, 4:37 am, zuhair <zaljo...(a)gmail.com> wrote: > Hi all, > > In the last one month I've posted many topics on cardinality. This one > is also another trial to define cardinality in ZF, i.e. without > Choice. > > First from T. Jeck's paper, it appears that his proof can be > generalized to every well orderable set x. > > So for every well order-able set x, there exist the set of all > sets hereditarily subnumerous to x. > > This is a theorem of ZF. > > Now this time the main idea of the trial is to associate a unique > ordinal with each set in ZF such that all sets equinumerous to each > other have a corresponding unique ordinal. > > So for example lets take any set x, then all sets equinumerous to x > would be associated with the same ordinal d(x), now every y that are > strictly subnumerous to x would be associated with an ordinal > d(y) that is also strictly subnumerous to d(x), same thing applies > every set z that is strictly supernumerous to x would be associated > with an ordinal d(z) that is strictly supernumerous to d(x). > > Next step we define for every x, the set of all sets hereditarily > subnumerous to d(x) (i.e. the set of all sets that are subnumerous > (injective) to d(x) were every member of their transitive closures is > also subnumerous to d(x) ) > > Lets denote this set as H(d(x)) > > Then we define cardinality as: > > Cardinality (x) is the class of d(x) and of all subsets of H(d(x)) > that are equinumerous to x. > > The point is how to define d(x). > > This is a trial: > > Define(d(x)): > > A=d(x) <-> for all y ( y e A <-> > Exist u,z( u strictly subnumerous to x & z=d(u) & > & y is ordinal & y equinumerous to d > (u))). > > This is a trick really, > > Now we start with x=0 i.e. x is the empty set. > > we'll see that d(0) = 0, because there do not exist any set u that is > strictly subnumerous to 0 > > so d(0)=0. > > Now d(x) were x is singleton would be 1 i.e. {0} > > So for every finite set x, d(x) would be the ordinal that is > equinumerous to x, i.e. the Von Neumann cardinal of x. > > Also for every Countably infinite set x, d(x) would be Omega. > > However for Aleph_1 , d(x) = Aleph_1 itself. > > Actually we can conclude that for every ordinal x, d(x) is the Von > Neumann Cardinal of x. > > Now lets take Power(omega) and lets assume it is incomparable to any > of the uncountable ordinals. > > Now d(power(omega))=Aleph_1 > d(power(power(omega)))=Aleph_2 > etc.... > > so we managed to define d(x) for every set x. > > Of course it is easy to prove that d(x) is not empty for every set x > in ZF. > > So now we come to our Cardinal here. > > Lets take the Cardinality of Power(omega) and lets assume that power > omega is not comparable to any of the uncountable ordinals. > > Now we have H(Aleph_1) as a set in ZF. > > So the cardinality of power(omega) is the class having Aleph_1 as a > member and also having all subsets of H(Aleph_1) that are equinumerous > to Power(omega) as members. > > Now The cardinality of Aleph_1 would be the class of all subsets of H > (Aleph_1) that are equinumerous to Aleph_1. > > Clearly they are not the same cardinality, since all proper subsets of > aleph_1 that are equinumerous to Aleph_1 would be members of the > Cardinality of Aleph_1, but not of the Cardinality of > Power(omega)). > > Now from the other hand, two sets that are equinumerous, it is obvious > that they will have the same cardinality, because the will have the > same d(x), and the rest of the sets in their cardinal are equinumerous > to each of them. so they will have the same cardinal. > > two sets that are strictly non equinumerous will also have different > cardinals also since their members would not be equinumerous. > > so: > > (1)Card(x)=Card(y) iff x and y have the same members(Extensionality). > > (2)Card(x) > Card (y) iff [(every member of Card(x) is strictly > supernumerous to every member of Card (y)) and (every > subset of d(x) that is equinumerous to d(x) is a member of Card(x) iff > every subset of d(y) that is equinumerous to d(y) is a member of Card > (y)) ]. > > (3)Card(x) < Card(y) <-> Card(y) > Card(x) > > (4)Card(x) incomparable with Card(y) iff non of the above. > > Although very complex definition but I think it works. > > Of course this definition requires Regularity, so it works in ZF, it > doesn't require choice. > > However I have the guess, that this definition can be modified to > exclude Regularity also. An example of such modification is: Card(x) is the set of d(x) and all subsets of d(x) that are equinumerous to x. However the problem with this definition would be sets that are not well orderable that are not comparable at the same time. If we stipulate that every two non well orderable sets are comparable (having an injection from one to the other) then this definition seems to work, but I don't know if this is equivalent to choice really. > > Zuhair
From: Rupert on 1 Jan 2010 06:02 On Jan 1, 8:37 pm, zuhair <zaljo...(a)gmail.com> wrote: > Hi all, > > In the last one month I've posted many topics on cardinality. This one > is also another trial to define cardinality in ZF, i.e. without > Choice. > > First from T. Jeck's paper, it appears that his proof can be > generalized to every well orderable set x. > > So for every well order-able set x, there exist the set of all > sets hereditarily subnumerous to x. > > This is a theorem of ZF. > > Now this time the main idea of the trial is to associate a unique > ordinal with each set in ZF such that all sets equinumerous to each > other have a corresponding unique ordinal. > > So for example lets take any set x, then all sets equinumerous to x > would be associated with the same ordinal d(x), now every y that are > strictly subnumerous to x would be associated with an ordinal > d(y) that is also strictly subnumerous to d(x), same thing applies > every set z that is strictly supernumerous to x would be associated > with an ordinal d(z) that is strictly supernumerous to d(x). > If ZF is consistent, then you cannot define such a function d(x) and prove in ZF that it has the requisite properties. Because, if ZF is consistent, then it is consistent with ZF that there exists a set S of real numbers which is Tarski infinite but Dedekind finite. Then if k and l are two natural numbers with k<l, the set S with l elements removed is subnumerous to the set S with k elements removed but not equinumerous with it. If it were possible to define your function d(x) then this would yield an infinite descending sequence of ordinals and so a contradiction. So working in ZF alone it will not be possible to do this.
From: David Libert on 2 Jan 2010 03:32 zuhair (zaljohar(a)gmail.com) writes: > On Jan 1, 4:37=A0am, zuhair <zaljo...(a)gmail.com> wrote: >> Hi all, >> >> In the last one month I've posted many topics on cardinality. This one >> is also another trial to define cardinality in ZF, i.e. without >> Choice. >> >> First from T. Jeck's paper, it appears that his proof can be >> generalized to every well orderable set x. >> >> So for every well order-able set x, there exist the set of all >> sets hereditarily subnumerous to x. >> >> This is a theorem of ZF. >> >> Now this time the main idea of the trial is to associate a unique >> ordinal with each set in ZF such that all sets equinumerous to each >> other have a corresponding unique ordinal. >> >> So for example lets take any set x, then all sets equinumerous to x >> would be associated with the same ordinal d(x), now every y that are >> strictly subnumerous to x would be associated with an ordinal >> d(y) that is also strictly subnumerous to d(x), same thing applies >> every set z that is strictly supernumerous to x would be associated >> with an ordinal d(z) that is strictly supernumerous to d(x). Rupert already reponded on this point, for a Dedekind set the strictly subnumerous sets below are not well-founded so this can't be done all levels down in that case. >> Next step we define for every x, the set of all sets hereditarily >> subnumerous to d(x) (i.e. the set of all sets that are subnumerous >> (injective) to d(x) were every member of their transitive closures is >> also subnumerous to d(x) ) >> >> Lets denote this set as H(d(x)) >> >> Then we define cardinality as: >> >> Cardinality (x) is the class of d(x) and of all subsets of H(d(x)) >> that are equinumerous to x. How do we show this cardinality is non-empty? If it can become empty for 2 nonisomorphic x then we get the old problem of nonisomorphic sets being assigned the same cardinality. Inspired by your definition above I make these definitions. Define a set is 0-well-orderable <-> it is well-orderable in the usual sense. For alpha an ordinal define inductively from 0 base case above a set x is alpha-well-orderable <-> it x is isomorphic to some set y such that for every member z of y there exists beta < alpha such that y is beta-well-orderable. If your Cardinality(x) above is nonempty, then x is isomorphic to some set y a subset of H(d(x)). Each element z of such a y is a member of H(d(x)), and so is subnumerous to ordinal d(x) and hence well-orderable, ie 0-well-orderable in my new terminology. So x is isomoprphic to y with all members 0-well-orderable. So x is 1-well-orderable. ZF proves AC <-> every set is 0-well-founded. Is it possible to have a ZF model with some set x which is not 1-well-founded? I don't know. But if it were such x would have empty Cardinality in the new definition. So a proof would have to rule out this possibility. Show from ZF or whatever extra axioms you want to use every set is 1-well-orderable. >> The point is how to define d(x). >> >> This is a trial: >> >> Define(d(x)): Somehow a system along the way has replaced spaces by other characters which makes the original quote hard to read. I will manually edit those back to spaces, but I might make mistakes and change your original spacing. >> A= d(x) <-> for all y ( y e A <-> >> Exist u,z( u strictly subnumerous to x > & z=d(u) & >> & y is ordinal & y equinumerous to d >> (u))). >> >> This is a trick really, The form of your defintion is a transfinite induction over strictly subnumerous, since you invoke d(u). Rupert already gave examples where this is not well-founded. We could interpret your definition as just defining d for sets with well founded strictly subnumerous relation below them. So maybe it is only defining cardinality for a subclass of the universe. This raises another interesting question. Is it possible to have in a ZF model a set x which cannot be well-ordered, with well-founded strictly subnumerous partial ordering below it? I don't know. Anyway, if it is and some cases of x get d(x) defined this way, then my previous question for these of why Cardinality(x) is non-empty remains. Below you discuss example of familar small x. I will delete that because it doesn't touch on the 2 trickier questions I just mentioned. [Deletion} >> Lets take the Cardinality of Power(omega) and lets assume that power >> omega is not comparable to any of the uncountable ordinals. >> >> Now we have H(Aleph_1) as a set in ZF. By the way, you are also using the generalized Jech result as you mentioned, but that used regualrity. Below you will consider what happens with definitions like this without regularity. My first model of those discussed recently got H(= 1) a proper class. So this is another difficulty for the version dropping regularity. [Deletion] >> two sets that are strictly non equinumerous will also have different >> cardinals also since their members would not be equinumerous. Except the emptiness issue above if it goes the wrong way. >> so: >> >> (1)Card(x)=3DCard(y) iff x and y have the same members(Extensionality). >> >> (2)Card(x) > Card (y) iff [(every member of Card(x) is strictly >> supernumerous to every member of Card (y)) and =A0(every >> subset of d(x) that is equinumerous to d(x) is a member of Card(x) iff >> every subset of d(y) that is equinumerous to d(y) is a member of Card >> (y)) ]. >> >> (3)Card(x) < Card(y) <-> Card(y) > Card(x) >> >> (4)Card(x) incomparable with Card(y) iff non of the above. >> >> Although very complex definition but I think it works. >> >> Of course this definition requires Regularity, so it works in ZF, it >> doesn't require choice. Yes, about regularity as I mentioned above and you say now. >> However I have the guess, that this definition can be modified to >> exclude Regularity also. > > An example of such modification is: > > Card(x) is the set of d(x) and all subsets of d(x) that are > equinumerous to x. > > However the problem with this definition would be sets that are not > well orderable that are not comparable at the same time. > > If we stipulate that every two non well orderable sets are comparable > (having an injection from one to the other) then this definition seems > to work, but I don't know if this is equivalent to choice really. > > >> >> Zuhair I think I have a proof over ZF that your last suggested property is equivalent to AC. AC -> everything is well-orderable, so your clause about non-well-orderable set is vacuous. So AC -> your stipulation is easy. For the other direction, your stipulation -> AC: Assume your stipulation. Suppose also A and B are arbitrary sets which cannot be well-ordered. I will derive a property of them I will state after discussion. Let alpha be the usual Hartog's number for B, defined by injections. Namely alpha is the least ordinal which cannot inject into B. ZF (no AC needed) proves there is such an ordinal alpha and it is a set, not a proper class. Without loss of generality I will assume A is disjoint from alpha. (Else replace A by a suitable isomorphic copy). Consider the sets B and A union alpha. A union alpha cannot be well-ordered, otherwise this woud induce a well-ordering on A, contrary to assumption on A. So your stipulation applies to B and A union alpha, so one of these must inject into the other. But if A union alpha injects into B, this would induce an injection of alpha into B, contrary to alpha being the injective Hartog numbwer for B. So B must inject into A union alpha. Pulling back preimages of A and alpha along this injection. we conclude the property I state now: B can be partitioned into a subset isomorphic to a subset of A and a subset which is well-orderable. This for any pair A, B both non-well-orderable. Next, consider any A which cannot be well-ordered. Let beta be the surjective Hartog number for A. This is the least ordinal which cannot surject onto A. ZF (no AC needed) proves this ordinal exists and is a set and not a proper class. I wrote abopit that in [1] David Libert "A new definition of Cardinality" sci.logic, sci.math Nov 24, 2009 http://groups.google.com/group/sci.logic/msg/23d5368fc03e61ca I quote that: > ZF proves for any set x there is a set of what I will call >the surjective Hartog ordinal. The usual definition of the >Hartog ordinal of a set x is the least ordinal which does >not inject into x. ZF proves the so called Hartog ordinal >exists and is a set. > > I take instead a surjecive version: the least ordinal >alpha such that x does not surject onto alpha. > > ZF proves there is always such a set sized ordinal. Namely >to see this, any surjection of x onto alpha induces an >equivalence realtiion on x : x elements are equivalent >if they are sent to the same ordinal. > > So any ordinal surejcted by x is isomorphic to a well-ordering >on some subset of P(x), ie pull the wellordering onn the ordinal >back to the equivalence class preimages. > > So all the ordinals less than the surjective Hartog ordinal of >x are ismimorphic to various well-orderings on a single set >P(x). > > So the collection of all well-orderings on P(x) has natural >well ordeing greater than all these, so its von Neuman ordinal >can't be surjected by x, so there is a least such. That quote locally called that surjective Hartog ordinal alpha, but I will resume calling the surjective Hartog ordinal for A beta, to avoid confusion with the previous alpha I used above in this proof. So A is an arbitrary non-well-orderable set, and beta is A's surejctive Hartog number. Let B = A x beta. If B could be well ordered, it would induce a well-ordering on A by an isomporphic copy of A sitting as a slice in B. This contrary to A not being well-orderable. So apply my last statement to this A, B. Conclude B has a subset isomorphic to a subset of A and it compliment in B well-orderable. Let A' be that subset of B, isomorphic to a subset of A. First suppose every A copy slice inside B has members in A'. Ie for each gamma < beta, A x {gamma} as a subset of B has nonempty intersection with A'. A' is isomorphic to a subset of A. So for the A members in that subset, map to A' and then map to the gamma where they live. For A members outside the subset if any just map to ordinal 0. Sonce we are for the moment assuming every slice gamma has some A' members, this map is surjective onto beta. We just surjected A onto beta, contrary to beta being the surjective Hartog ordinal for A. We conclude some gamma slice of B is disjoint from A'. So the entire A copy on slice gamma was instead sent to B - A', the set which is well-orderable. This well ordering induces a well-ordering on its subset the gamma'th slice, which being isomprphic to A induces a well-ordering on A. Contrary to A not being well-orderable. We got this contradiction by assuming your stipulation and also assuming some A cannot be well-ordered. So every wset can be well-ordered, hence AC, from the assumption of your stipulation. Another point. I did my models of ZF - regualrity with cardinality undefinable. For the momeent those seem to be ok. So what is this about seeking a definition of cardinality in ZF - regularity? Do you mean to add some axioms to that? Or do you mean really just ZF - regularity, and you are still questioning those models? -- David Libert ah170(a)FreeNet.Carleton.CA
From: zuhair on 2 Jan 2010 09:30 On Jan 2, 3:32 am, ah...(a)FreeNet.Carleton.CA (David Libert) wrote: > zuhair (zaljo...(a)gmail.com) writes: > Another point. I did my models of ZF - regualrity with > cardinality undefinable. For the momeent those seem to be > ok. > > So what is this about seeking a definition of cardinality > in ZF - regularity? Do you mean to add some axioms to that? > Or do you mean really just ZF - regularity, and you are > still questioning those models? I need some time to study these models. And If I understand them, then I shall reply in a separate post to address them. But let me clarify my point of view: Suppose we add Cardinality symbolized by "| |" as a primitive to the language of ZF minus Reg., so"| |" would be a primitive one place function symbol. Let's name this theory ZF minus Reg.(=,e,| |) to differentiate it from ZF minus Reg. And suppose we add the following axiom to the list of axioms of ZF minus Reg.(=,e,| |). Axiom of Cardinality: For all x,y : |x|=|y| <-> Exist f ( f:x-->y , f is bijective ) So now we have the theory ZF minus Reg.+Axiom of Cardinality(=,e,| |). Now according to your models, then ZF minus Reg.+ Axiom of Cardinality (=,e,| |). is not equi-interpretable with ZF minus Reg. What I want to come with is a definition of Cardinality that work in a model of ZF minus Reg. that is equi-interpretable with ZF minus Reg.+Axiom of Cardinality(=,e,| |). So for example I want to come with a "definition of Cardinality" in ZF minus Reg. suppose that was, for a specific formula Phi(x): Card(x) <-> Phi(x) Then I will add the axiom: Axiom of Cardinality: For all x Exist y ( y=Card(x) ). So we'll have ZF minus Reg. + Axiom of Cardinality. Now what I want is that ZF minus Reg. + Axiom of Cardinality Equi-interpretable with ZF minus Reg. + Axiom of Cardinality (e,=,| | ). Can that be done? Can we have a defined cardinality that is as general as the primitive cardinality in a model of ZF minus Regularity. I noticed that the primitive concept of Cardinality can even work with proper classes, something that I can hardly imagine defined cardinality can achieve? But for now I am speaking about Cardinality of sets and not of proper classes. In nutshell I want the most general definition of cardinality in ZF minus Regularity one can get. Zuhair > > -- > David Libert ah...(a)FreeNet.Carleton.CA
|
Next
|
Last
Pages: 1 2 3 4 5 6 Prev: Fitch's paradox and OWA Next: Cardinality and Hereditary sets. |