Prev: How can I be sure that de L'Hopitals rule doesn't hide some solutions
Next: Bret's Law of Sig Figs
From: Kaba on 17 Jan 2010 06:29 Arturo Magidin wrote: > Now, for the OP: > > Since f must send positive numbers to positive numbers, it must > respect order: let r and s be real numbers. Then r<s if and only if s- > r>0 if and only if f(s-r) > 0 (the converse follows from the > argument above by considering f^{-1}) if and only if f(s)-f(r)>0, if > and only if f(r)<f(s). > > To show your f is the identity, let x be an arbitrary real number; try > finding monotonic sequences over which you have control that converge > to x, and see what happens to their images. Let d be a metric in R. Pick x in R and find a convergent sequence (x_n) in (R, d) such that x_n in Q and lim_{n->oo} x_n = x A convergent sequence is also a Cauchy sequence. Thus: for all epsilon > 0: exists N: for all n, m > N: d(x_n, x_m) < epsilon I already proved for all q in Q: f(q) = q Thus (f(x_n)) is also a Cauchy sequence in (R, d). By completeness of R, (f(x_n)) converges to some value s. I would now have to see that actually s = lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) = f(x) Find a non-decreasing sequence (x_n) that converges to x. Then: for all epsilon > 0: exists x_eps in Q: x - epsilon < x_eps < x Because (x_n) is monotonically convergent to x: exists N: for all n > N: x_n >= x_eps => (for all q in Q: f(q) = q) exists N: for all n > N: f(x_n) >= f(x_eps) => (f preserves order) lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) >= f(x_eps) => (epsilon arbitrary) lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) >= f(x) However, because of monotonicity of (x_n) we also know x_n <= x => f is order preserving f(x_n) <= f(x) => lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) <= f(x) Thus by totality lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) = f(x) Then f(x) = lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) = lim_{n->oo} x_n = x Is that ok? -- http://kaba.hilvi.org
From: Arturo Magidin on 18 Jan 2010 00:05 On Jan 17, 5:29 am, Kaba <n...(a)here.com> wrote: > Arturo Magidin wrote: > > Now, for the OP: > > > Since f must send positive numbers to positive numbers, it must > > respect order: let r and s be real numbers. Then r<s if and only if s- > > r>0 if and only if f(s-r) > 0 (the converse follows from the > > argument above by considering f^{-1}) if and only if f(s)-f(r)>0, if > > and only if f(r)<f(s). > > > To show your f is the identity, let x be an arbitrary real number; try > > finding monotonic sequences over which you have control that converge > > to x, and see what happens to their images. > > Let d be a metric in R. You don't get to pick a metric here. Use the standard distance metric. > Pick x in R and find a convergent sequence (x_n) > in (R, d) such that Do *I* have to find one, or should you, the one who wants to prove the theorem, find it? And, since your metric was just *some* metric, what makes you think that you can find such a sequence? I can come up with plenty of metrics on R for which such a thing does not exist (e.g., the discrete metric). > x_n in Q and > lim_{n->oo} x_n = x > > A convergent sequence is also a Cauchy sequence. Thus: > for all epsilon > 0: exists N: for all n, m > N: > d(x_n, x_m) < epsilon > > I already proved > for all q in Q: f(q) = q > > Thus (f(x_n)) is also a Cauchy sequence in (R, d). By completeness of R, Again: since you simply said that d was *a* metric on R, you have no grounds for claiming that R is complete *with respect to d*. So this step is a non-sequitur because of how you set things up. You picked *a* metric on R. > (f(x_n)) converges to some value s. I would now have to see that > actually > > s = lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) = f(x) You have no grounds for claiming that the limit of the images of the x_i is the image of x. Nor did you use the fact that the sequence was increasing. So why did you define it as increasing? > > Find a non-decreasing sequence (x_n) that converges to x. Then: > > for all epsilon > 0: exists x_eps in Q: > x - epsilon < x_eps < x > > Because (x_n) is monotonically convergent to x: > exists N: for all n > N: x_n >= x_eps What is "x_eps"? > => (for all q in Q: f(q) = q) > exists N: for all n > N: f(x_n) >= f(x_eps) > => (f preserves order) > lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) >= f(x_eps) > => (epsilon arbitrary) > lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) >= f(x) > > However, because of monotonicity of (x_n) we also know > x_n <= x > => f is order preserving > f(x_n) <= f(x) > => > lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) <= f(x) > > Thus by totality > lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) = f(x) > > Then > f(x) = lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) = lim_{n->oo} x_n = x > > Is that ok? It is utterly confused, beginning with your idea of picking "a" metric for R, and overly complicated. Take x, and let x_n and y_n be increasing and decreasing sequences of rationals, respectively, that converge to x. Then x_n <= x <= y_n for all n, hence since f respects order, f(x_n) = x_n <= f(x) <= f(y_n) = y_n for all n (since f(q) = q for all rationals q). Since this holds for all n, you have that x = lim(x_n) <= lim(f(x)) <= lim(y_n) = x. -- Arturo Magidin
From: William Elliot on 18 Jan 2010 03:44 On Sat, 16 Jan 2010, Kaba wrote: > (Question at the end where the proof stumps on) > > Let > * R be the set of real numbers, > * Q be the set of rational numbers, > * N be the set of natural numbers, > * Z be the set of integers, and > * f be a field automorphism in R. > You may weaken f to for all x,y, f(xy) = f(x).f(y) some r with f(r) /= 0 for all x, f(x + r) = f(x). After you've shown f|Q = id_Q, ie f restricted to Q is the identity map, show f is an increasing surjection, hence continuous and being the identity on a dense set, f is the identity for the whole set. > Claim: > f is the identity function: f(x) = x > > Proof: > 1) for all x: > f(x) = f(1 * x) = f(1) * f(x) > => f(1) = 1 > > 2) for all x: > f(x) = f(x + 0) = f(x) + f(0) > => f(0) = 0 > > 3) f(2) = f(1 + 1) = f(1) + f(1) = 2 > By induction, for all n in N: f(n) = n > > 4) for all x: > 0 = f(0) = f(x + (-x)) = f(x) + f(-x) > => f(-x) = -f(x) > > 5) for all z in Z, z < 0: > f(-z) = -f(z) = -z > > 6) for all x != 0: > 1 = f(1) = f(x / x) = f(x) * f(1 / x) > => f(1 / x) = 1 / f(x) > > 7) for all q = (n / m) in Q: > (n, m in Z, m != 0) > f(n / m) = f(n) * f(1 / m) = f(n) / f(m) = n / m > > How do I prove f(x) = x for real numbers? > > -- > http://kaba.hilvi.org >
From: Kaba on 18 Jan 2010 04:50 Arturo Magidin wrote: > > Let d be a metric in R. > > You don't get to pick a metric here. Use the standard distance metric. Right, I thought I could generalize the metric but I can't. Let d be the standard metric. > > Pick x in R and find a convergent sequence (x_n) > > in (R, d) such that > > Do *I* have to find one, or should you, the one who wants to prove the > theorem, find it? And, since your metric was just *some* metric, what > makes you think that you can find such a sequence? I can come up with > plenty of metrics on R for which such a thing does not exist (e.g., > the discrete metric). It means I pushed this as a sub-problem, assuming I can do that, and see what follows. With d changed it should now hold. > > x_n in Q and > > lim_{n->oo} x_n = x > > > > A convergent sequence is also a Cauchy sequence. Thus: > > for all epsilon > 0: exists N: for all n, m > N: > > d(x_n, x_m) < epsilon > > > > I already proved > > for all q in Q: f(q) = q > > > > Thus (f(x_n)) is also a Cauchy sequence in (R, d). By completeness of R, > > Again: since you simply said that d was *a* metric on R, you have no > grounds for claiming that R is complete *with respect to d*. So this > step is a non-sequitur because of how you set things up. Yep, fixed with changing d. > > (f(x_n)) converges to some value s. I would now have to see that > > actually > > > > s = lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) = f(x) > > You have no grounds for claiming that the limit of the images of the > x_i is the image of x. Nor did you use the fact that the sequence was > increasing. So why did you define it as increasing? I am not claiming that. I am saying that the next thing I need to prove is that thing. I did not yet define it as increasing. > > Find a non-decreasing sequence (x_n) that converges to x. Then: Here I add the property of being non-decreasing to (x_n). > > for all epsilon > 0: exists x_eps in Q: > > x - epsilon < x_eps < x Here I define "x_eps". > > Because (x_n) is monotonically convergent to x: > > exists N: for all n > N: x_n >= x_eps > > What is "x_eps"? See above. > > => (for all q in Q: f(q) = q) > > exists N: for all n > N: f(x_n) >= f(x_eps) > > => (f preserves order) > > lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) >= f(x_eps) > > => (epsilon arbitrary) > > lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) >= f(x) > > > > However, because of monotonicity of (x_n) we also know > > x_n <= x > > => f is order preserving > > f(x_n) <= f(x) > > => > > lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) <= f(x) > > > > Thus by totality > > lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) = f(x) > > > > Then > > f(x) = lim_{n->oo} f(x_n) = lim_{n->oo} x_n = x The above then follows. I.e. after changing d to the standard metric it seems to me my proof is ok, even if unnecessary complex. Do you agree? > It is utterly confused, beginning with your idea of picking "a" metric > for R, and overly complicated. > > Take x, and let x_n and y_n be increasing and decreasing sequences of > rationals, respectively, that converge to x. Then x_n <= x <= y_n for > all n, hence since f respects order, f(x_n) = x_n <= f(x) <= f(y_n) = > y_n for all n (since f(q) = q for all rationals q). Since this holds > for all n, you have that x = lim(x_n) <= lim(f(x)) <= lim(y_n) = x. That is much cleaner. -- http://kaba.hilvi.org
From: achille on 18 Jan 2010 08:06 On Jan 18, 5:50 pm, Kaba <n...(a)here.com> wrote: > > The above then follows. I.e. after changing d to the standard metric it > seems to me my proof is ok, even if unnecessary complex. Do you agree? > > --http://kaba.hilvi.org How about using the fact f is order preserving [*], If f(x) <> x at any point x, pick a rational number r between x and f(x), then case1) x < f(x) => x < r AND f(x) > f(r). case2) f(x) < x => r < x AND f(r) > f(x). both cases contradict with [*], so f(x) = x for all x. Since
First
|
Prev
|
Next
|
Last
Pages: 1 2 3 4 Prev: How can I be sure that de L'Hopitals rule doesn't hide some solutions Next: Bret's Law of Sig Figs |