From: Tony Orlow on
Virgil wrote:
> In article <457c658c$1(a)news2.lightlink.com>,
> Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
>
>> David Marcus wrote:
>>> Tony Orlow wrote:
>>>> David Marcus wrote:
>>>>> Tony Orlow wrote:
>
>>>>>> I don't need to construct these numbers. Consider them
>>>>>> axiomatically declared.
>>>>> Then list the axioms for them.
>>>> (sigh)
>>>>
>>>> infinite(x) <-> A yeR x>y
>>> Is that your only axiom? If so, then state your first theorem about
>>> them and give the proof.
>>>
>> That's the only one necessary for what defining a positive infinite
>> n.
>
> It is a definition, not an axiom. And as it does not imply existence of
> anything, one has no more that other axioms will supply.
>
>
>

Since it is a statement of implication, it's a rule, and an axiom. That
it serves as the definition of infinite doesn't make it not a rule for
determining what values are infinite, once finites are defined.

>> A whole array of theorems pop forth from infinite-case induction
>> and IFR, such as that the size of the even naturals is half that of
>> the naturals.
>
> Not unless you declare them as axioms, as neither holds without being
> assumed.

If n>k -> f(n) (inductively proven), and infinite(n) -> n>k, then
infinite(n) -> f(n), and the property can be said to hold in the
infinite case. I suppose what you want is an exact statement of IFR so
that we can determine which inductive proofs are allowable? Or, what?
From: Tony Orlow on
Virgil wrote:
> In article <457c48ef(a)news2.lightlink.com>,
> Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
>
>> Odd powers of i equal i
>
> Or -i.
>
> For integers n,
>
> i^(4*n + 1) = 1
>
> but
>
> i^(4*n - 1) = -1
>
> Try learning some arithmetic before pontificating.

Well, if that wasn't about as out of context as it could be. You must be
really bored.
From: stephen on
Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
> David Marcus wrote:
>> Tony Orlow wrote:
>>> David Marcus wrote:
>>>> Tony Orlow wrote:
>>>>> David Marcus wrote:
>>>>>> Tony Orlow wrote:
>>>>>>> Why do you have a problem with the mere suggestion of an infinite value?
>>>>>> I don't have a problem with infinite values. However, you have to do
>>>>>> more than merely say "positive infinite n". Assuming your positive
>>>>>> infinite things aren't the same as something that we already know about
>>>>>> (in which case, you should just say so), you either need to give a
>>>>>> construction of these positive infinite things or you need to specify
>>>>>> their properties. You haven't done either. For example, how many of
>>>>>> these things are there? How do they relate to each other? How do they
>>>>>> interact with the natural numbers? Are the operations of addition and
>>>>>> multiplication defined for them?
>>>>> Well, I have been through much of that regarding such specific language
>>>>> approaches as the T-riffic digital numbers, but that's not necessary for
>>>>> this purpose. It suffices to say that, if a statement is proved true for
>>>>> all n greater than some finite k, that that also includes any postulated
>>>>> infinite values of n, since they are greater than any finite k. I don't
>>>>> need to construct these numbers. Consider them axiomatically declared.
>>>> Then list the axioms for them.
>>> (sigh)
>>>
>>> infinite(x) <-> A yeR x>y
>>
>> Is that your only axiom? If so, then state your first theorem about them
>> and give the proof.
>>

> That's the only one necessary for what defining a positive infinite n. A
> whole array of theorems pop forth from infinite-case induction and IFR,
> such as that the size of the even naturals is half that of the naturals.
> That's a no-brainer. Go back to where I first answered your question at
> length, and read again, at length. It's not transfinitology, but it's
> also not nonsense.

> Allow me to add another:

> |{ x| yeR and 0<(x-y)<=1}|=Big'un.

> That's the unit infinity.

What is the definition of | | ?

Stephen
From: Tony Orlow on
Virgil wrote:
> In article <457c1fa0(a)news2.lightlink.com>,
> Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
>
>> Virgil wrote:
>>> In article <457b8ccf(a)news2.lightlink.com>,
>>> Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
>>>
>>>> Virgil wrote:
>>>>> In article <457b5606(a)news2.lightlink.com>,
>>>>> Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
>>>>>
>>>>>> David Marcus wrote:
>>>>>>> Tony Orlow wrote:
>>>>>>>> David Marcus wrote:
>>>>>>>>> Tony Orlow wrote:
>>>>>>>>>> There is nothing wrong with saying E and N have the same
>>>>>>>>>> cardinality.
>>>>>>>>>> It's a fact. Six Letters is essentially suggesting IFR, my Inverse
>>>>>>>>>> Function Rule, which indeed can parametrically compare sets mapped
>>>>>>>>>> onto
>>>>>>>>>> the real line, using real valued functions, as a generalization to
>>>>>>>>>> set
>>>>>>>>>> density. It works for finite and infinite sets. So, what is wrong
>>>>>>>>>> with
>>>>>>>>>> trying to form a more cohesive theory of infinite set size, which
>>>>>>>>>> distinguishes set sizes that cardinality cannot? There certainly
>>>>>>>>>> seems
>>>>>>>>>> to be intuitive impetus for such a theory.
>>>>>>>>> Fine. Please state your rule. Let's take a look.
>>>>>>>> I've been over this a lot, but hey, what's one more time. Practice
>>>>>>>> makes
>>>>>>>> perfect.
>>>>>>>>
>>>>>>>> We start with the notion of infinite-case induction, such that a
>>>>>>>> equation proven true for all n greater than some finite k holds also
>>>>>>>> for
>>>>>>>> any positive infinite n.
>>>>>>> What is a "positive infinite n"?
>>>>>>>
>>>>>> A value greater than any finite value.
>>>>> But if "n", is, as usual, reserved for indicating natural numbers, those
>>>>> which are members of every inductive set, there is no such thing.
>>>>>
>>>> What, now mathematics has declared what the single letter n means? It's
>>>> a variable.
>>> Every variable has a domain of definition. The variable 'n' is quite
>>> commonly required to have the set of finite naturals as its domain.
>>>
>>> I merely remarked that when that is the case, there are no values for n
>>> other than finite ones.
>>>
>>>>>> Why do you have a problem with the mere suggestion of an infinite value?
>>>>> It is arithmetical operations with infinite values absent any
>>>>> definition of what those operations mean or what properties they have,
>>>>> to which we make legitimate objections.
>>>>>
>>>> Not really.
>>> Really.
>>>
>> No. Reread the following:
>>
>>>> If the expressions used can themselves be ordered using
>>>> infinite-case induction, then we can say that one is greater than the
>>>> other, even if we may not be able to add or multiply them. Of course,
>>>> most such arithmetic expressions can be very easily added or multiplied
>>>> with most others. Can you think of two expressions on n which cannot be
>>>> added or multiplied?
>>> I can think of legitimate operations for integer operations that cannot
>>> be performed for infinites, such as omega - 1.
>> Omega is illegitimate schlock. Read Robinson and see what happens when
>> omega-1<omega.
>
> I have read Robinson. On what page of what book does he refer to omega -
> 1 in comparison to omega? I do not find any such reference.

He uses the assumption that any infinite number can have a finite number
subtracted, and become smaller, like any number except 0, so there is no
smallest infinite, just like you do with the endless finites.
Non-Standard Analysis, Section 3.1.1:

"There is no smallest infinite number. For if a is infinite then a<>0,
hence a=b+1 (the corresponding fact being true in N). But b cannot be
finite, for then a would be finite. Hence, there exists an infinite
numbers [sic] which is smaller than a."

Of course, he has no for omega. It's illegitimate schlock, like I said.

>>>>>> Surely you must have guessed enough what I meant to follow the
>>>>>> paragraph? (sigh)
>>>>> Guessing is not a reliable way of finding things out.
>>>> Of course, reading is a little more reliable, but when one gets stuck on
>>>> such words as "positive" and "infinite", maybe one needs to do a little
>>>> guessing.
>>> If TO's descriptive powers are so insubstantial as to leave us
>>> perpetually guessing what he means, he will never be able to convey
>>> anything of mathematical interest or significance.
>> If you don't know what "positive" or "infinite" mean, that's not my fault.
>
> My uncertainty about what TO means by a term is directly TO's fault.

Is it your dog's fault when he doesn't understand when you explain how
the microwave works?

> I know what mathematics usually means by many terms, but as TO
> frequently does not mean the same thing by any mathematical term as
> mathematics means, I cannot say that I know what TO means by them.

Oh.
From: Tony Orlow on
Virgil wrote:
> In article <457c1eb6(a)news2.lightlink.com>,
> Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
>
>> Bob Kolker wrote:
>>> Virgil wrote:
>>>
>>>> In article <457b8a2f(a)news2.lightlink.com>,
>>>> Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com> wrote:
>>>>
>>>>
>>>>> Language is a set of strings from an alphabet.
>>>>
>>>> Like Chinese and Japanese?
>>>>
>>>> Languages are acoustic at first, and are still learnt that way.
>>>> Ideogramatics comes later.
>>> All languages (used by humans in general discourse) are acoustic because
>>> they are primarily spoken and heard. Writing of any kind is a very
>>> recent development (in the last 6000 years or so). You are refering to
>>> the writing systems. It turns out that Japanese has two phonetic
>>> alphabets (Katakana and Hirugana) but the Chinese style ideographs
>>> (Kanjii) are preferred for traditional reasons. If the Japanese wished
>>> to, they could use a totally phonetic graphology. They just do not want to.
>>>
>>> The Chinese have used ideograms for much longer, but there is a phonetic
>>> system for representing the Mandarin pronounciation. The problem with
>>> Chinese is there are so many dialects which are mutually incompatable
>>> the only common written language is ideographic. The Japanese are under
>>> no such constraint.
>>>
>>> The alphabet derived from the Phonecian graphology was originally
>>> ideographic. The letters were pictures (or highly stylized
>>> representations) of things that eventually took on conventional sound
>>> values.
>>>
>>> Bob Kolker
>>>
>> You guys both need to take your meds, and take note of a few facts.
>>
>> 1) While a symbol is generally considered to be a visual pattern, it is
>> most generally any uniquely distinguishable sensory input. It could be
>> an auditory sound, a latin letter, arabic numberal, hieroglyph, or asian
>> pictogram. It can be a series of beeps and clicks, like Morse code.
>>
>> 2) While Western languages have a small alphabet, and words with an
>> averga of a large number of characters, one can have a large alphabet,
>> the size of the entire vocabulary, where each word is a single
>> character. So, Asian pictographic languages is not excluded by that
>> definition.
>>
>> 3) I have specifically been talking about digital number systems, which
>> are a special case of languages, complete, and with a unique
>> quantitative interpretation for any finite string. It doesn't help to
>> wander off into sociological and psychological realms when discussing
>> digital number system.
>
> Digital number representations are not languages, as they consist of
> only proper nouns, with no verbs, adjectives adverbs pronouns, etc.

A formal language is a set of strings:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Formal_language
I suppose now you're going to tell me I'm using nonstandard language....