From: George Greene on
On May 29, 9:31 pm, Charlie-Boo <shymath...(a)gmail.com> wrote:

> Can't define "It is a finite set."?  ~(all X)(eY)P(Y) ^ LT(X,Y)
>
> C-B

That 's not even grammatical.
You haven't said what P() means.
Nobody knows what language you're speaking.
The rest of us were speaking ZFC, in which "LT" simply
does not occur. Trust me, you have no hope of defining
this in any simpler language.

In your string above, which letter is supposed to represent the
set that may or may not be finite? Is it X ? If it is, then
a definition of finite can't possibly begin with ~(all X).
Maybe you better learn how to define stuff.
A definition of "finite", if you abbreviated "finite" as F(.),
would look like
Ax[F(x) <--> some other stuff about x ]

From: George Greene on
On May 29, 9:32 pm, Charlie-Boo <shymath...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
> Or you mean a finite set in general?  Who said it can't be defined?
> (What a great challenge!)

It can be defined at least 5 or 6 different ways in ZF.
In ZFC, these different ways are not different after all.
There is a famous post about it that I re-cite from time
to time, just so it doesn't get lost in antiquity.
But it is all in rather abstruse ZF, which you of course
can't be bothered to bother with.
From: George Greene on
On May 29, 9:32 pm, Charlie-Boo <shymath...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
> Or you mean a finite set in general?

Yes. I mean, if you have a set theory, where you are talking about
an infinite number of sets, some of which are finite, how do you tell
specifically which are finite and which are not??

> Who said it can't be defined?
> (What a great challenge!)

AK was the one who told me it couldn't be defined
IN FIRST-ORDER LOGIC FROM A RECURSIVE AXIOM-SET.
If you use more powerful machinery then (of course) more things
are possible. My point in the original argument was that if
something NEEDS more than first-order logic, then that something
cannot be "trivial".

Here are 5 different meetings of your "challenge" (you need to start
here):
This was originally from Herman Rubin in sci.math.


If X and Y are sets, then we define X <= Y
if either of the equivalent definitions hold:

(1) There is a one-to-one function from X into Y.
(2) There is a one-to-one function from a subset of X onto Y.

If X and Y are sets, write X == Y (actually written with a single pair
of wavy lines, and read X is equipollent to Y) if either of the two
equivalent conditions below hold:

(1) X <= Y and Y <= X
(2) There is a 1-1 function from X onto Y.

If X and Y are sets, then write X < Y if X <= Y and not X == Y.

If X is a set, define "X+1" to be any set Y containing X such that
Y\X is a singleton. (As used, it won't matter which set is used, and
the axiom of choice will not be required in any of the proofs, but
this is NOT obvious. There is, however, a formal definition that
will work, but I don't need to go into that much detail at this time.)

If X is a non-empty set, define "X-1" to be any subset of X with only
one element removed. (Again, the axiom of choice will not be required
in any of the proofs, but, this time, there is no suitable formal
definition.)

Define X <=_* Y if any of the equivalent definitions below hold:

(1) X is empty, or there is a function from Y onto X.
(2) There is a function from a subset of Y onto X.
(3) There is a function from Y+1 onto X+1.

If X is a set, define P(X) (usually written with a script P) to be the
power set of X, the collection of all subsets of X.

"omega" will be the first infinite ordinal. (Ordinal numbers are
defined in such a way that "n" = {0, 1, 2, ..., n-1}. I don't think
I need to go into the details of the definition.)

X is n-finite (n for normal) if any of the following equivalent
definitions hold:

(1) X is equipollent to a finite ordinal.
(2) X < omega
(3) P(X) is PD-finite
(4) P(X) is D*-finite
(5) P(P(X)) is D-finite

X is A-finite if for any subset Y of X, Y is n-finite or X\Y is
n-finite. (A stands for amorphous.)

X is PD-infinite if P(X) is D-infinite (defined below).

X is D*-infinite if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:

(1) There is a proper subset Y of X such that X <=* Y
(2) X <=* X-1
(3) X+1 <=* X
(4) omega <=* X (oops, that's not quite the same but 1-3 imply 4)

X is D-infinte (Dedekind-infinite) if any of the following equivalent
conditions hold:

(1) There is a proper subset Y of X such that X <= Y
(2) There is a proper subset Y of X such that X == Y
(3) X+1 <= X
(4) X+1 == X
(5) X <= X-1
(6) X == X-1
(7) omega <= X

It can be seen that, for any set X, with the following definitions,
(1) -> (2) -> (3) -> (4) -> (5) -> (6)
(1) X is D-infinite
(2) X is D*-infinite
(3) X is D*-infinite (definition 4, but I don't have a separate
name)
(4) X is PD-infinite
(5) X is A-infinite
(6) X is n-infinite

(BTW, some of the lemmas used are:

(A) If X <=_* Y, then P(X) <= P(Y).
(B) If X is n-infinite, then P(X) is D*-infinite
(C) If X is D*-infinite, then P(X) is D-infinite.)

With more effort and a lot of knowledge of set theory, one can show
that
none of these implications is reversable.

For some background, including the definitions of <=, and <=_*, I
recommend _Set Theory for the Mathematician_, by Jean E. Rubin. I
have
a vague memory of a paper by one or more Rubin's about relationships
between definitions of finiteness, but I can't find a reference at the
moment.