From: David Bernier on
Penny Hassett wrote:
> JSH wrote:
>>
>>> As an example, when I look up your Prime Residue Axiom* I get
>>>
>>> ## Given differing primes p1 and p2, where p1 > p2, there is no
>>> preference for any particular residue of p2 for p1 mod p2 over any
>>> other.
>>>
>>> Now consider the following Hypothesis proposed by my cat
>>>
>>> Socratic Prime Residue Hypothesis
>>>
>>> ## For any sufficiently large prime number p, p+i is always composite if
>>> i is less than p^(1/p) but the probability of p+i being prime is
>>> independent of i if i is greater than p^(1/p).
>>
>> Huh? I'd guess that p^{1/p} would be roughly 1? So why not just
>> write 1?
>>
>> Simplify. See?
>>
>> Simplify your argument and ask again, please.
>>
>>> Does your Axiom disprove his Hypothesis? I think they can both be true
>>> unless you can show me otherwise.
>
> You're right, I must have misunderstood what he said. Perhaps I should
> have written ...
>
>
> As an example, when I look up your Prime Residue Axiom* I get
>
> ## Given differing primes p1 and p2, where p1 > p2, there is no
> preference for any particular residue of p2 for p1 mod p2 over any other.
>
> Now consider the following Hypothesis proposed by my cat
>
> Socratic Prime Residue Hypothesis
>
> ## For any sufficiently large prime number p, p+i is always composite if
> i is less than p^(1/100) but the probability of p+i being prime is
> independent of i if i is greater than p^(1/100).

I don't know if your cat is aware of new results on small prime gaps from 2005.
On the arXiv website, there's a pre-print by Goldston, Pintz and Yildirim
announcing the unconditional result:
liminf_{n -> oo} (p_{n+1} - p_n)/log(p_n) = 0.

In words:
<< there are arbitrarily large primes that are �unusually
close � together. >>

At arXiv:
< http://arxiv.org/abs/math/0508185 >

For large p, p^(1/100) should be much larger than log(p), so perhaps
the Socratic Prime Residue Hypothesis is too strong.


David Bernier

From: MichaelW on
On Jul 19, 9:06 am, David Bernier <david...(a)videotron.ca> wrote:
> Penny Hassett wrote:
> > JSH wrote:
>
> >>> As an example, when I look up your Prime Residue Axiom* I get
>
> >>> ## Given differing primes p1 and p2, where p1 > p2, there is no
> >>> preference for any particular residue of p2 for p1 mod p2 over any
> >>> other.
>
> >>> Now consider the following Hypothesis proposed by my cat
>
> >>> Socratic Prime Residue Hypothesis
>
> >>> ## For any sufficiently large prime number p, p+i is always composite if
> >>> i is less than p^(1/p) but the probability of p+i being prime is
> >>> independent of i if i is greater than p^(1/p).
>
> >> Huh? I'd guess that p^{1/p} would be roughly 1? So why not just
> >> write 1?
>
> >> Simplify. See?
>
> >> Simplify your argument and ask again, please.
>
> >>> Does your Axiom disprove his Hypothesis? I think they can both be true
> >>> unless you can show me otherwise.
>
> > You're right, I must have misunderstood what he said. Perhaps I should
> > have written ...
>
> > As an example, when I look up your Prime Residue Axiom* I get
>
> > ## Given differing primes p1 and p2, where p1 > p2, there is no
> > preference for any particular residue of p2 for p1 mod p2 over any other.
>
> > Now consider the following Hypothesis proposed by my cat
>
> > Socratic Prime Residue Hypothesis
>
> > ## For any sufficiently large prime number p, p+i is always composite if
> > i is less than p^(1/100) but the probability of p+i being prime is
> > independent of i if i is greater than p^(1/100).
>
> I don't know if your cat is aware of new results on small prime gaps from 2005.
> On the arXiv website, there's a pre-print by Goldston, Pintz and Yildirim
> announcing the unconditional result:
>      liminf_{n -> oo} (p_{n+1} - p_n)/log(p_n) =  0.
>
> In words:
> << there are arbitrarily large primes that are “unusually
> close ” together. >>
>
> At arXiv:
> <http://arxiv.org/abs/math/0508185>
>
> For large p, p^(1/100) should be much larger than log(p), so perhaps
> the Socratic Prime Residue Hypothesis is too strong.
>
> David Bernier

David,

Thanks for the reference. I am trying to absorb the article now and
find that it mentions the "level of distribution of primes". I don't
understand the term and Google has not been my friend. Are you able to
provide a link and/or explanation?

Regards, Michael W.
From: Joshua Cranmer on
On 07/18/2010 04:20 PM, JSH wrote:
> So you think that if p is large enough that p mod 3 might decide that
> it should NOT be 1 or -1, when say p mod 5 is not 0?

It's not impossible.

> If primes do not work together to block that eventuality then a twin
> prime WILL occur whenever it is the case that for all odd primes less
> than sqrt(p), it is NOT true that -2 is a residue modulo p.

If they don't. You don't have any evidence other than "it doesn't seem
like it should be so" (in other words, "I say so").

> Don't get it? I use humanizing the primes to point out what they
> CANNOT do.

That is a very interesting definition of "humanizing" then, given what
you say below...

> Primes are not human beings.

"To humanize" generally means "to give or cause to have the fundamental
properties of a human." This often has the connotation of ascribing
human foibles to things which generally don't appear to have them. One
such foible, that you love to refer to a lot, is collusion. So if you
are ascribing human characteristics, such as the ability to collude, to
an inanimate number, what is to say that two numbers cannot "collude"?

--
Beware of bugs in the above code; I have only proved it correct, not
tried it. -- Donald E. Knuth
From: JSH on
On Jul 18, 5:48 pm, Joshua Cranmer <Pidgeo...(a)verizon.invalid> wrote:
> On 07/18/2010 04:20 PM, JSH wrote:
>
> > So you think that if p is large enough that p mod 3 might decide that
> > it should NOT be 1 or -1, when say p mod 5 is not 0?
>
> It's not impossible.

I should have had p mod 5 is not -2.

So the issue is, if p is large enough, can it be the case that p mod 3
will never be -1, if p - 2 mod 5 is not 0.

You assertion--assuming you were thinking of the correct value for p
mod 5 versus what I put in error--is that it's not impossible.

> > If primes do not work together to block that eventuality then a twin
> > prime WILL occur whenever it is the case that for all odd primes less
> > than sqrt(p), it is NOT true that -2 is a residue modulo p.
>
> If they don't. You don't have any evidence other than "it doesn't seem
> like it should be so" (in other words, "I say so").

So you hypothesize chains of primes working together relative to each
other with rules like if p mod 3 = 2, then p mod 5 must equal 3?

That rule by itself would disprove the Twin Primes Conjecture if it
were enforced.

> > Don't get it?  I use humanizing the primes to point out what they
> > CANNOT do.
>
> That is a very interesting definition of "humanizing" then, given what
> you say below...
>
> > Primes are not human beings.
>
> "To humanize" generally means "to give or cause to have the fundamental
> properties of a human." This often has the connotation of ascribing
> human foibles to things which generally don't appear to have them. One
> such foible, that you love to refer to a lot, is collusion. So if you
> are ascribing human characteristics, such as the ability to collude, to
> an inanimate number, what is to say that two numbers cannot "collude"?

Numbers don't collude. They're numbers. Primes are primes.

3 and 5 do not work together to block twin primes from existing
because they like you and really want to help you with your argument.
They aren't considerate of your feelings and anxious to do what's
necessary to remove those ornery twin primes that will pop up if they
just can't understand your need to feel right.

3 and 5 cannot feel your pain.


James Harris
From: David Bernier on
MichaelW wrote:
> On Jul 19, 9:06 am, David Bernier<david...(a)videotron.ca> wrote:
>> Penny Hassett wrote:
>>> JSH wrote:
>>
>>>>> As an example, when I look up your Prime Residue Axiom* I get
>>
>>>>> ## Given differing primes p1 and p2, where p1> p2, there is no
>>>>> preference for any particular residue of p2 for p1 mod p2 over any
>>>>> other.
>>
>>>>> Now consider the following Hypothesis proposed by my cat
>>
>>>>> Socratic Prime Residue Hypothesis
>>
>>>>> ## For any sufficiently large prime number p, p+i is always composite if
>>>>> i is less than p^(1/p) but the probability of p+i being prime is
>>>>> independent of i if i is greater than p^(1/p).
>>
>>>> Huh? I'd guess that p^{1/p} would be roughly 1? So why not just
>>>> write 1?
>>
>>>> Simplify. See?
>>
>>>> Simplify your argument and ask again, please.
>>
>>>>> Does your Axiom disprove his Hypothesis? I think they can both be true
>>>>> unless you can show me otherwise.
>>
>>> You're right, I must have misunderstood what he said. Perhaps I should
>>> have written ...
>>
>>> As an example, when I look up your Prime Residue Axiom* I get
>>
>>> ## Given differing primes p1 and p2, where p1> p2, there is no
>>> preference for any particular residue of p2 for p1 mod p2 over any other.
>>
>>> Now consider the following Hypothesis proposed by my cat
>>
>>> Socratic Prime Residue Hypothesis
>>
>>> ## For any sufficiently large prime number p, p+i is always composite if
>>> i is less than p^(1/100) but the probability of p+i being prime is
>>> independent of i if i is greater than p^(1/100).
>>
>> I don't know if your cat is aware of new results on small prime gaps from 2005.
>> On the arXiv website, there's a pre-print by Goldston, Pintz and Yildirim
>> announcing the unconditional result:
>> liminf_{n -> oo} (p_{n+1} - p_n)/log(p_n) = 0.
>>
>> In words:
>> << there are arbitrarily large primes that are �unusually
>> close � together.>>
>>
>> At arXiv:
>> <http://arxiv.org/abs/math/0508185>
>>
>> For large p, p^(1/100) should be much larger than log(p), so perhaps
>> the Socratic Prime Residue Hypothesis is too strong.
>>
>> David Bernier
>
> David,
>
> Thanks for the reference. I am trying to absorb the article now and
> find that it mentions the "level of distribution of primes". I don't
> understand the term and Google has not been my friend. Are you able to
> provide a link and/or explanation?

For 0< theta < 1, the primes have level of distribution theta
if their distribution in various congruence classes is relatively
un-skewed. For a number q >= 1, there are phi(q) congruence
classes modulo q that are susceptible to containing
infinitely many primes. If q = 10, phi(10) = 4 because there are four
numbers from 1 to 10 co-prime with 10: 1, 3, 7 and 9.

Bombieri proved that theta=1/2 is true in the inequality (1.3)
of the Goldston, Pintz and Yildirim paper ("level theta" is
introduced there by: "We say that [...] level theta [...]",
so it may be uncommon usage).

Probably a good place to start is to read Wikipedia's article
on Dirichlet's Theorem:
<
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Dirichlet's_theorem_on_primes_in_arithmetic_progressions>

I think Dirichlet only proved that all phi(q) admissible congruence
classes contain infinitely many primes. For results on
the distribution, even for the trivial progression
1, 2, 3, .... (q = 1), the Prime Number Theorem
was only proved in 1896. The article on
PNT says that de la Vall�e Poussin also proved
PNT for primes in arithmetic progressions:
< http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Prime_number_theorem >.

The Elliott-Halberstam Conjecture is about the best that
can be hoped for: any theta < 1 works.

The article on the Elliott-Halberstam Conjecture shows how
maximum discrepancies from the average are added up
and compared to a reference number which grows with x.

< http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Elliott�Halberstam_conjecture > .

According to Goldston, Pintz and Yildirim, theta = 1/2 in
their (1.3) is the statement of Bombieri-Vinogradov
Theorem (however in (1.1) they give the weight log(n)
to the prime n, whereas the pi(x) prime-counting
function gives a weight 1 to every prime).

David Bernier