From: Marc Alcobé García on
> It seems odd unless one looks at the particular technical mechanics of it.

I know it maybe is too much to ask, but could you briefly sketch these
technical details?

The original question was:

>What is exactly V?

You said:

> In Z (and its offshoots such as ZF), we have a theorem:
> ~ExAy(y=y -> yex).

> Now, if we then use abstraction notation to write:
> {y | y=y}
> and define a constant 'V' by
> V = {y | y=y}
> then we find that the set abstraction "term" does not properly refer
> and so the definition of 'V' is not proper.

I am not sure what you mean with the sentence 'the set abstraction
"term" does not properly refer
and so the definition of 'V' is not proper'

> Therefore, how one takes the term 'V' depends on ones handling of
> improperly referring terms. I (and a good number of authors) prefer to
> use the Fregean method, so that, TECHNICALLY, V = 0.

I wonder at which level that assignment is done.

> However, we also recognize that we may refer to such notation as 'V'
> and {y | y=y} as either shorthand, or (by more intricate syntactical
> methods, as defined terminology that reduces to
> META-language about FORMULAS of Z set theory.

Yes, Levy's approach is that every formula containing class terms (in
a language that is a conservative extension of the basic language of
set theory) is equivalent to another formula in the basic language of
set theory, but I do not see how could that help in understanding the
nature of V.
From: MoeBlee on
On Feb 5, 6:56 am, Marc Alcobé García <malc...(a)gmail.com> wrote:

> You said:
>
> > it might help to be clear where the relativization method is
> > being used not to prove consistency itself, but rather RELATIVE
> > consistency
>
> and also gave an example of statements of consistency and relative
> consistency.
>
> My question is: when is a consistency proof using relativization not a
> relative consistency proof?

When the theorem proved is not a relative consistency assertion but
rather a plain conistency assertion.

> Can these kinds of proof be distinguished?

Yes, by what the theorem proved is. If the theorem is a plain
consistency statement then the proof is a plain consistency proof. If
the theorem is a relative consistency statement, then the proof is
relative consistency proof.

MoeBlee



From: MoeBlee on
On Feb 5, 7:45 am, Marc Alcobé García <malc...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
> > It seems odd unless one looks at the particular technical mechanics of it.
>
> I know it maybe is too much to ask, but could you briefly sketch these
> technical details?

To save a lot of typing, I would much rather recommend Suppes's
'Introduction To Logic' as including the best introduction to the
subject of definitions in mathematics. I would guess that a used copy
would be available at a pretty cheap price on the Internet. Or, if you
like, tell me what books on mathematical logic and/or set theory you
have; then, if one of those books covers the subject, I'll direct you
to the relevant pages.

> The original question was:
>
> >What is exactly V?
>
> You said:
>
> > In Z (and its offshoots such as ZF), we have a theorem:
> > ~ExAy(y=y -> yex).
> > Now, if we then use abstraction notation to write:
> > {y | y=y}
> > and define a constant 'V' by
> > V = {y | y=y}
> > then we find that the set abstraction "term" does not properly refer
> > and so the definition of 'V' is not proper.
>
> I am not sure what you mean with the sentence 'the set abstraction
> "term" does not properly refer
> and so the definition of 'V' is not proper'

Set abstraction terms of the form:

{y | P}

where 'P' is a formula.

The set abstraction term does not properly refer when

~ExAy(yex <-> P).

For example (and I'm in context of ZF unless otherwise stated in this
conversation):

~ExAy(yex <-> y=y).

> > Therefore, how one takes the term 'V' depends on ones handling of
> > improperly referring terms. I (and a good number of authors) prefer to
> > use the Fregean method, so that, TECHNICALLY, V = 0.
>
> I wonder at which level that assignment is done.

There are different variations in handling this that might occur at
the object level or the meta-level depending on the details of the
handling.

> > However, we also recognize that we may refer to such notation as 'V'
> > and {y | y=y} as either shorthand, or (by more intricate syntactical
> > methods, as defined terminology that reduces to
> > META-language about FORMULAS of Z set theory.
>
> Yes, Levy's approach is that every formula containing class terms (in
> a language that is a conservative extension of the basic language of
> set theory) is equivalent to another formula in the basic language of
> set theory, but I do not see how could that help in understanding the
> nature of V.

The point was to deal with the TERM 'V' defined by '{y | y=y}' when
the theory does not provide, for example, ExAy(yex <-> y=y).

In Bernays class theory (and its basic variants) it's easy to say what
V is. In that context, V is the class of all sets. But in ZF, there is
no object of which every set is a member; so, in that context, IF 'V'
is added to the actual language as a 0-place operation symbol, then,
if we wish not to leave loose ends dangling ("terms with no
reference"), then we confront how to deal with the term 'V'.

MoeBlee

From: Marc Alcobé García on
On 5 feb, 16:43, MoeBlee <jazzm...(a)hotmail.com> wrote:
> On Feb 5, 6:56 am, Marc Alcobé García <malc...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
>
> > You said:
>
> > > it might help to be clear where the relativization method is
> > > being used not to prove consistency itself, but rather RELATIVE
> > > consistency
>
> > and also gave an example of statements of consistency and relative
> > consistency.
>
> > My question is: when is a consistency proof using relativization not a
> > relative consistency proof?
>
> When the theorem proved is not a relative consistency assertion but
> rather a plain conistency assertion.
>
> > Can these kinds of proof be distinguished?
>
> Yes, by what the theorem proved is. If the theorem is a plain
> consistency statement then the proof is a plain consistency proof. If
> the theorem is a relative consistency statement, then the proof is
> relative consistency proof.
>
> MoeBlee

Maybe this ought to be obvious but I'll take the risk of asking: what
distinguishes a plain consistency statement from relative consistency
one?

If T is any first-order theory we might ask if T is consistent. Then,
I guess Con(T) could be considered as a plain consistency statement
(at the level of the metatheory). To prove it, one can make use of set
theory and try to find a structure where the (nonlogical) axioms of T
are true.

Now, if we try to do the same with a statement such as Con(ZF) we find
ourselves using the very same theory whose consistency we are trying
to prove. It is at this point that I really get lost.

From: MoeBlee on

> Maybe this ought to be obvious but I'll take the risk of asking: what
> distinguishes a plain consistency statement from relative consistency
> one?

I answered this twice already.

A plain consistency statement is of the form:

T is consistent.

A relatvie consistncy statement is of the form:

If T is consistent then T* is consistent.

> If T is any first-order theory we might ask if T is consistent. Then,
> I guess Con(T) could be considered as a plain consistency statement

Yes, and a relative consistency statement is of the form:

Con(T) -> Con(T*)

> Now, if we try to do the same with a statement such as Con(ZF) we find
> ourselves using the very same theory whose consistency we are trying
> to prove. It is at this point that I really get lost.

But we DON'T try to prove 'Con(ZF)' in ZF.

MoeBlee