From: Archimedes Plutonium on


Archimedes Plutonium wrote:
> > [0] Michael *Hardy* and Catherine Woodgold,
> > "*Prime* *Simplicity*",  *Mathematical
> > Intelligencer<https://mail.google.com/wiki/Mathematical_Intelligencer>

--- quoting from Mathematical Intelligencer MI of Ore's direct proof
---

page 65 of
Øystein Ore’s book Number Theory and Its History [104]:
Euclid’s proof runs as follows. Let a;b;c;...;k be any
family of prime numbers. Take their product P ¼ ab...k
and add 1. Then P + 1 is either a prime or not a prime.
If it is, we have added another prime to those given. If it
is not, it must be divisible by some prime p. But p cannot
be identical with any of the given prime numbers
a;b;...;k because then it would divide P and also P + 1;
hence it would divide their difference, which is 1, and
this is impossible. Therefore a new prime can always be
found to any given (finite) set of primes.
Within this argument, we do find one small lemma
proved by contradiction.

--- end quoting ---

Now I was thinking that we never really needed any reductio ad
absurdum
anywhere and anyplace in the full Direct Euclid Infinitude of Primes.
Can I
make that so? I think so, for mine own direct method proofs have no
contradiction. And as I wrote them in the early or mid 1990s I used
the
unique prime factorization theorem(UPFAT). I am sure that Euclid was
privy to
UPFAT and that every Direct method uses UPFAT, only we glide past
saying so.

One of the reasons that I like to give "reasons" alongside the
statements is to
keep me on track. Here are my most recent Direct Method in both
shortform and
longform:


Euclid's IP, Direct or constructive in short-form goes like this:
1) Definition of prime
2) Given any finite set of primes
3) Multiply the lot and add 1 (Euclid's number) which I call W+1
4) Either W+1 is prime or we conduct a prime factor search
5) this new prime increases the set cardinality by one more prime
6) since this operation of increasing set cardinality occurs for any
given
finite set we start with, means the primes are infinite set.

Notice in step 4 of shortform, we know that either W+1 or a factor of
W+1 has a prime which is not in the finite list at the start and we
know
this from UPFAT. So UPFAT eliminates the need to do what Ore or even
Euclid did, since when we invoke UPFAT, and we cannot escape from
invoking UPFAT as Euclid invokes UPFAT and Ore invokes UPFAT.

The Unique Prime Factorization theorem tells us that either W+1 is
prime
or has a prime factor. So the only thing remaining is to mechanically
fetch
the new prime and we do that by taking the square root of W+1 and
going through
all the primes less than or equal to the square root of W+1.


DIRECT Method (constructive method), long-form; Infinitude of Primes
Proof


(1) Definition of prime as a positive integer divisible
only by itself and 1.


(2) Statement: Given any finite collection of primes
2,3,5,7,11, ..,p_n possessing a cardinality n Reason: given


(3) Statement: we find another prime by considering W+1 =(2x3x...xpn)
+1 Reason: can always operate on given numbers


(4) Statement: Either W+1 itself is a prime Reason: numbers are
either
unit, composite or prime


(5) Statement: Or else it has a prime factor not equal to any of the
2,3,...,pn
Reason: numbers are either unit, composite or prime


(6) Statement: If W+1 is not prime, we find that prime factor Reason:
We take the square root of W+1 and
we do a prime search through all the primes from 2 to
square-root of W+1 until we find that prime factor which
evenly divides W+1


(7) Statement: Thus the cardinality of every finite set can be
increased. Reason: from steps (3) through (6)


(8) Statement: Since all/any finite cardinality set can be increased
by one more prime, therefore the set of primes is an infinite set.
Reason:
going from the existential logical quantifier to the universal
quantification


Now I can improve the above in that statements 4,5 have the reasons of
Unique
Prime Factorization theorem.

Some where along the long road of writing those proofs I deleted the
UPFAT, only to
see that I now need it to streamline the Direct method.

In the Direct method, no lemma is needed and no lemma having a
argument
of contradiction is needed. In the Direct method, it is all a
constructive method. The so
called lemma of Ore as stipulated by the authors Hardy/Woodgold, was
excess baggage
and that the either P+1 was prime or had a prime factor comes not from
having a reductio
ad absurdum but comes from UPFAT.

I am convinced, only there can never be a proof of this, but convinced
that in Ancient Greek times, and fairly common today in math circles,
is that the expression "suppose false.." is a
expression commonly blurted out and with no bearing to the proof at
hand. Just as is
the expression "absolutely so" or the expression "without a doubt". So
I think what happened
is that Euclid or the translators of Euclid, filled in spaces in the
proof with expressions such
"suppose false.." Expressions that fill in between sentences or
phrases. And that the expression "suppose false.." was not a method
that Euclid was engaged in, but merely some
words that leads him into further steps of the proof.

An expression in modern times of math proofs is the expression "this
further implies..."
Now when seeing the word "implies" in a proof, one can mistakenly
think it is the logical
implication, and it may well be, but often it is just the
mathematician using common words
to push along his argument.

Now any one of us can take any easy test. We can pick up a proof and
see how easy it is
to insert the phrase "suppose not true.." Almost with any math proof
we are reading, we can
insert that phrase and although it does not launch a reductio ad
absurdum lemma at that
point of the proof write-up, it still looks like it fits in that spot
of the proof.

So what I am saying is that in Euclid's proof or in Ore's proof, both
needed to say that
either P+1 is prime or has a prime factor and the reason is UPFAT, but
if you do not say
UPFAT, you can mislead yourself by saying "suppose false, then the 1
between P and P+1
is divisable.

Summary: I am convinced that no lemma of reductio ad absurdum is ever
needed in the
Direct/Constructive proof. I suspect that in Ancient Greek times the
expression
"suppose false.." was an expression of common usage and did not mean
that the
mathematician was launching a reductio ad absurdum.

Archimedes Plutonium
http://www.iw.net/~a_plutonium/
whole entire Universe is just one big atom
where dots of the electron-dot-cloud are galaxies
From: sttscitrans on
On 30 June, 09:00, Archimedes Plutonium
<plutonium.archime...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
> Archimedes Plutonium wrote:
> > > [0] Michael *Hardy* and Catherine Woodgold,
> > > "*Prime* *Simplicity*",  *Mathematical
> > >
> So what I am saying is that in Euclid's proof or in Ore's proof, both
> needed to say that
> either P+1 is prime or has a prime factor and the reason is UPFAT, but
> if you do not say
> UPFAT, you can mislead yourself by saying "suppose false, then the 1
> between P and P+1
> is divisable.

No proof whether direct or indirect will go through unless
you can exclude the possibility that the integer following
w= "some product of primes" or the "product of all primes assumed to
exist" etc. is a unit i.e. has no prime divisors.
The essence of this proof is that no two consecutive integers
share a prime divisor. Whatever w+1 might be, you know it must
have at least one prime divisor that is not a prime divisor of w
otherwise GCD(w,w+1) <> 1.
If w is the product of all primes you have a contradiction, there are
no other primes that could divide w+1 without gcd(w,w+1)<> 1. If w is
some product of primes then w+1 must be divisible by some other prime
or primes.

I am surprised it has taken you 20 years to realize this.