From: Lester Zick on
On Thu, 27 Dec 2007 11:03:35 -0800 (PST), David R Tribble
<david(a)tribble.com> wrote:

>David R Tribble wrote:
>> Alternatives to "not" are other logical operators.
>> Or are you saying that's not the case?
>
>Lester Zick wrote:
>> I'm saying "not" is not unary just as differences are not unary and
>> are taken between things and can stand by itself as a well formed
>> logical statement.
>
>The only thing that can stand by itself in a logical statement
>is a simple value, such as "true". "Not" is not a value, it's an
>operator, and therefore cannot "stand by itself".

"Not" is a predicate and can be analyzed on that basis alone in terms
of itself for the purpose of determining whether it is true or self
contradictory in combination with other predicates or itself.

>Differences are values, not operators. They are the result
>of applying a binary difference operator to two arguments
>(operands). The statement "d = a - b" has a value, d,
>equated to the result of a binary operator "-" taking two
>arguments, a and b.
>
>I can't see how "not = (whatever)" can be a well-formed sentence.
>What is "not" equal to as a value? It is equal to false?

You can always make any predicate a sentence just by prefixing it with
"it is".

~v~~
From: Lester Zick on
On Thu, 27 Dec 2007 11:03:35 -0800 (PST), David R Tribble
<david(a)tribble.com> wrote:

>Lester Zick wrote:
>> You're interested in Y only because assumptions of truth can be false.
>
>David R Tribble wrote:
>> If by "assumptions of truth" you mean "axioms", no, that's not
>> the case. Mathematical axioms are always true.
>
>Lester Zick wrote:
>> Incorrect by your own words. You say elsewhere:
>> "An axiom is an assumed truth. Period."
>> "Assumed truth" and "always true" are different predicates.
>
>Let's just expand that, then, to:
> Axioms are statements of truth, and are always true, and are
> therefore always assumed to be true (obviously).

So you're seriously suggesting the predicates "assumed to be true" and
"are always true" mean the same? In your example you've got it exactly
backward. If an axiom is true we can certainly assume it to be true.
But the reverse is not true that what you assume true, mathematically
or otherwise, is always true. I can certainly think of any number of
"assumptions of truth" which are not "always true" and even "not ever
true".

>If an axiom is assumed to be false, it is not an axiom.
>In other words, a false statement cannot be an axiom.
>Hence axioms cannot be false.

You know, you really need a refresher course in Logic. You seem to
consider "assumptions" the only predicate present. It doesn't run that
way. "Axioms are either considered true or false" and then progress to
whether "false statements" can be axioms. The proper sequence is to
begin with "assumptions of truth" you label "axioms" and then analyze
whether they're "true" or "false" and hence whether they can be
considered axioms.

The problem is you never progress to the second step. You just begin
with "assumptions of truth" as axioms and let the matter rest because
you have no way to determine the truth of any assumption you make.

>You seem to be hung up on the "assumed" part.

Wouldn't any mathematician worthy of his salt get hung up with any
student who just "assumed" a theorem is true? The problem with your
use of "axiomatic assumptions of truth" is you have no way to analyze
whether they're true or not so you just assume they're true instead of
false. If you're going to use the predicate "true" whether assumed or
demonstrated, you have to be able to use the predicate "false" also.

~v~~
From: Lester Zick on
On Thu, 27 Dec 2007 11:03:35 -0800 (PST), David R Tribble
<david(a)tribble.com> wrote:

>David R Tribble wrote:
>> If by "assumptions of truth" you mean "definitions", no, that's
>> not the case either. Definitions are not true or false.
>
>Lester Zick wrote:
>> Well definitions are always definitions. Doesn't make them true or
>> false. Contradictions between predicates in definitions make them
>> false as in "squircles are square circles".
>
>Contradicting predicates makes a definition void or vacuous,
>but it does not make it false. Definitions are never false or true.

Except I don't understand the difference between vacuous, invalid,
void, invalid, incorrect, etc. and simply false. The only difference
between definitions and propositions is that the former just involve
isolated predicate combinations while the latter entail predicate
combinations from different sources.

>"Squircles are square circles" is a vacuous definition; there
>are no geometric objects that meet the definition of squircle.
>Yet the definition itself is neither true nor false; it just is.

However there are many definitions for which that would be true. You
can only recognize the vacuous nature of the definitions for squircles
on cursory inspection because everyone understands that squares are
different from circles in some fundamental way.

But if I simply said X is Y Z you would have no way to know that the
definition was valid, invalid, or simply false without analyzing each
of the predicates associated with Y and Z in combination to determine
whether there were any basic contradiction involved. In other words
you cannot just pronounce a definition valid, invalid, true, or false
without specialized knowledge.

>Consider "a Goldbach non-integer is an integer greater than
>2 that is not the sum of two primes". We don't know if there
>are any integers meeting this definition, but that does not
>make the definition false, or true, or unknown, or whatever.
>The definition itself is completely valid.

Unfortunately you have no way to know that without analyzing each and
every predicate in combination with each and every constituent
predicate to decide whether there's a mutual contradiction involved.

It may be that the predicates which characterize "sums" and "primes"
considered in combination with one another preclude a Goldbach non
integer. But we can't know that except through the evaluation of each
in combination with each and every other predicate in the definitions.

In other words there is no categorical distinction between definitions
and propositions in mathematics or anywhere else which precludes the
possibility of mutual contradiction between predicate combinations in
the aggregate of predicate combinations in definitions or propositions
because both are made up of predicates and predicate combinations.

Consequently any distinction between the two is artificial and there
is no reason to say one can be false and the other not to the extent
there can be mutual contradictions involved in each. In fact the only
relevant distinction I can think of is that false propositions do not
necessarily invalidate any of their constituent definitions although
there would have to be some mutual inconsistency among definitions.

In other words one might say that a false definition would entail self
contradiction and a false proposition mutual contradiction between
otherwise non self contradictory definitions. But even this concession
would not necessarily invalidate the possibility of self contradictory
predicates in definitions.

For that matter just consider the Peano axiomatic generation of the
naturals. You maintain points are isomorphic with the reals. However
the Peano axiomatic generation of the naturals doesn't say how it is
successive naturals are supposed to fall on any straight line in going
from point to point because there is no guarantee successive points
would lie in any particular direction. In fact the only way such a
thing could be possible is if you had the straight line to begin with
and successively divided it to produce the naturals. Hence I consider
the Peano axiomatic generation of the naturals invalid, incorrect, and
"false" to the extent it entails a false assumption: that a succession
of points has to lie in any specific direction.

~v~~
From: Lester Zick on
On Wed, 26 Dec 2007 11:49:31 -0700, Lester Zick
<dontbother(a)nowhere.net> wrote:

>>Take a can. Paint a vertical line on it.
>>
>>Roll it over a white sheet of paper along a line.
>>
>>You will get a number of points where the lines intersect.
>
>You're ignoring slippage.
>
>>The points have pi distance from each other
>>
>>provided the can had 1 in diameter.
>>
>>pi is tangible.
>
>Of course pi is tangible. That's not the problem. Pi lies on circular
>arcs not straight lines. That's the problem. And circular arcs are
>every bit as "tangible" whatever that may mean, as straight lines.
>
>There are infinitely many more points on curves than straight lines.
>That's why curves define transcendentals rather than merely square
>roots of rationals defined on straight lines. This is also the reason
>curves have variable tangents defined at only the point of tangency
>whereas straight lines have a constant tangent defined at all points
>on the line. And it's also the reason all straight lines are congruent
>with one another and curves of different types are not.
>
>I suspect you and others misunderstand the nature of the problem.
>Curves have variable tangents with different tangents at each point on
>the curve. Straight lines have a constant tangent at all points.
>
>This means ratios between curves and straight lines and square roots
>of rationals defined on them are not constant so that there can be no
>exact definition between any curve segment and straight line segment.
>
>The difficulty is that between any two points the only thing definable
>exactly between them are square roots of rationals because tangents
>are constant and the difference is linear. Which is what makes them
>straight lines to begin with. Curves on the other hand aren't straight
>lines because tangents are variable, which is what makes them curve.
>
>I won't suggest the problem here is peculiar to modern mathematics;
>however I don't think modern mathematics has helped comprehend the
>nature of the problem with its emphasis on arithmetic to the exclusion
>of geometry. The fact is you can approximate the length of curves in
>relation to the square roots of rationals but you can't commensurate
>them exactly because there are infinitely many more points on curves
>than straight lines and modern math hasn't facilitated the study of
>either class of infinity when modern mathematikers naively assume the
>existence of a "real number line" inclusive of all possible ratios for
>rationals and irrationals, together with the implication curves and
>straight lines have the same infinite number of points just because
>they're infinite.
>
>In other words there is one infinity of points associated with each
>straight line tangent and a different infinity of points associated
>with all infinities of variably different straight line tangents. And
>that's why there can be no exact commensuration between curves and
>straight lines. At best there can only be an exact commensuration
>between tangents to curves and straight lines.

I'd like to correct a misuse of terminology in my reply above which
might engender misunderstandings. Above I consistently refer to
points, infinities of points, relative sizes of those infinities, etc.
In doing this I was adopting the conventional vernacular and
perspective on points as constituents of lines just for simplicity
and not to argue that points are in fact constitutents of lines.

To be accurate what I should have said was "infinitesimals" instead of
points. Points have zero dimensionality; lines have zero width; and
surfaces zero thickness. Points delimit or define line segments; lines
delimit or define surfaces; and surfaces delimit or define solids.

And although points require no dimensionality to delimit or define
lines, lines themselves require an infinitesimal dimensionality to be
lines.There has to be some directionality associated with constituents
of lines and that directionality has to have a reciprocal relationship
between lines and their constituents. In other words derivatives of
lines are infinitesimals and conversely the integral of infinitesimals
constitute lines.

The same is true of lines with respect to surfaces and surfaces with
respect to solids. Lines have zero width with respect to the surfaces
they delimit or define. But surfaces are constituted of infinitesimals
integrated between lines which delimit those surfaces. And the same is
true of solids which are constituted of infinitesimals integrated
between surfaces which delimit or define those solids.

I hope this clarifies what might otherwise be misunderstood. The
relative magnitudes of infinities of infintesimals and not points is
what I had in mind and what I should have been describing. Points are
boundaries which define lines and are not constituents of them.

~v~~