From: Newberry on
On Mar 30, 3:30 am, stevendaryl3...(a)yahoo.com (Daryl McCullough)
wrote:
> Newberry says...
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
> >On Mar 29, 10:17=A0pm, Aatu Koskensilta <aatu.koskensi...(a)uta.fi> wrote:
> >> How are we to apply your ideas about vacuity, meaningfulness, truth,
> >> proof, what not, in context of the following mathematical observation:
> >> for any consistent theory T extending Robinson arithmetic, either
> >> directly or through an interpretation, in which statements of the form
> >> "the Diophantine equation D(x1, ..., xn) = 0 has no solutions" can
> >> be expressed, there are infinitely many Diophantine equations
> >> D(x1, ...,xn) = 0 that have no solutions but for which
> >> "the Diophantine equation D(x1, ..., xn) = 0 has no solutions"
> >> is not provable in T.
> >> On an ordinary understanding, a statement of the form "the Diophantine
> >> equation D(x1, ..., xn) = 0 has no solutions" is true just in case
> >> D(x1 ..., xn) = 0 has no solutions. According to your account some
> >> such statements are neither true nor false
>
> >No.
>
> What do you mean, no? You are proposing to equate truth and provability.
> Some sentences of the form "the Diophantine equation D(x1, ..., xn) = 0
> has no solutions" are neither provable nor refutable.

In which theory?

It follows from
> your equating of truth and provability that they are neither true nor
> false.
>
> The reasoning that there are statements that are true, but unprovable
> goes like this:
>
> 1. Let D(x1,...,xn) be a polynomial in the variables x1, ..., xn.
>
> 2. If m1, ..., mn are n integers such that D(m1,...,mn) = 0,
> then the statement "There exists x1, ..., xn such that D(x1,...,xn) = 0"
> is provable. We can easily prove this by plugging in m1, ..., mn and
> checking to see if the result is 0.
>
> 3. If the statement "There exists x1, ..., xn such that D(x1,...,xn) = 0"
> is not provable, then there are no integers m1, ..., mn such that
> D(m1, ..., mn) = 0. This follows immediately from 2.
>
> 4. Note that if Phi is the formula
> "There exists x1, ..., xn such that D(x1,...,xn) = 0",
> then 3. has the form: "If Phi is not provable, then ~Phi".
> In other words, if Phi is not provable, then the negation of Phi
> holds.
>
> 5. Therefore, if Phi is neither provable nor refutable, then
> the negation of Phi holds. So if Phi is neither provable nor
> refutable, then Phi is false. ("Phi is false" means the same
> thing as "The negation of Phi holds").
>
> 6. Therefore, if Phi is neither provable nor refutable, then
> there is a statement, Phi, that is false, but not provably false.
> There is another statement, ~Phi that is true, but not provable.
>
> 7. Therefore, if there is a statement Phi (of the appropriate
> form) that is neither provable nor refutable, then provability
> and truth are not the same.
>
> --
> Daryl McCullough
> Ithaca, NY- Hide quoted text -
>
> - Show quoted text -

From: Newberry on
On Mar 30, 6:07 am, "Jesse F. Hughes" <je...(a)phiwumbda.org> wrote:
> Newberry <newberr...(a)gmail.com> writes:
> > On Mar 28, 9:01 pm, "Jesse F. Hughes" <je...(a)phiwumbda.org> wrote:
> >> Newberry <newberr...(a)gmail.com> writes:
> >> > On Mar 28, 5:54 am, "Jesse F. Hughes" <je...(a)phiwumbda.org> wrote:
> >> >> Newberry <newberr...(a)gmail.com> writes:
>
> >> >> > But I can. In a system with gaps Tarski's theorem does not apply. We
> >> >> > can then simply equate truth with provability.
>
> >> >> Your second sentence does not follow.  You have to show that you have
> >> >> a logic in which provability turns out to be equivalent to truth.
> >> >> Tarski's theorem may not preclude this possibility, but it doesn't
> >> >> follow that you can then "simply equate truth with provability."
>
> >> > Did I say it follows? I meant that it is possible. In classical logic
> >> > withuot gaps it is impossible. Why did you not interpret what I said
> >> > this way?
>
> >> "We can then simply equate truth with provability."
>
> > It does automatically folow but we can nevertheless do that.
>
> You have to *show* that this can be done in your system.

And to a reasonable degree I have shown it. And I do NOT mean by
pointing out that Tarski does not apply.
 
>
> And, indeed, the word "equate" is still misleading, since it suggests
> that define true to mean "provable".  That can certainly be done.  I
> can say that, hereafter, when I say that a statement of PA is true, I
> mean that there is a proof of P in PA.  Of course, such semantic play
> is unsatisfactory.
>
> --
> "After years of arguing I realize that your intellects are too limited
> to fully grasp my work.  [...] Still, no matter how child-like your  
> minds are, [...] since you have language, [...] there's a chance that
> I'll be able to find something that your minds can handle." --JSH- Hide quoted text -
>
> - Show quoted text -

From: Newberry on
On Mar 30, 6:04 am, "Jesse F. Hughes" <je...(a)phiwumbda.org> wrote:
> Newberry <newberr...(a)gmail.com> writes:
> > Indeed. But if we leave out all the vacuous sentences we can still do
> > all the useful arithmetic as we know it. Although all the people on
> > this board believe that such sentences are true nobody argued that
> > they were useful. Aatu even said that they did not belong in ordinary
> > mathematical reasoning. Furthermore there is a reason to think that
> > they are neither true nor false. I cannot think of any good reason for
> > claiming that 1 + 1 = 2 is not true.
>
> You seem to have misrepresented Aatu's claims.  Moreover, you're just
> wrong.  I've argued repeatedly that some sentences of the form
>
>   ~(Ex)(P & Q)
>
> occur in ordinary mathematical reasoning (and hence are useful), even
> when (Ex)P is false.  An example occurred in sci.math recently.
>
> Simon C. Roberts gave a purported proof of FLT[1], by arguing:
>
> ~(En)(Ea,b,c)(a^n + b^n = c^n & a, b, c are pairwise coprime).
>
> Let's denote a^n + b^n = c^n by P(a,b,c,n) and a, b, c are pairwise
> coprime by Q(a,b,c), so that Simon's argument attempts to show that
>
>   c
>
> Of course, I am *not* claiming that he proved what he claims.  That's
> beside my point.  A poster named bill replied that (1) is not Fermat's
> last theorem[2], which has the form
>
>   ~(En)(Ea,b,c) P(a,b,c,n).                                         (2)
>
> Arturo responded[3] by proving
>
>   (En)(Ea,b,c) P(a,b,c,n) -> (En)(Ea,b,c)( P(a,b,c,n) & Q(a,b,c) ). (3)
>
> Hence, a proof of (1) yields a proof of (2) by modus tollens.

How about this?

(En)(Ea,b,c) P(a,b,c,n). Assumption
(En)(Ea,b,c) P(a,b,c,n) -> (En)(Ea,b,c)( P(a,b,c,n) & Q(a,b,c) ).
(3)
~(En)(Ea,b,c) P(a,b,c,n). Modus Tollens
~(En)(Ea,b,c) P(a,b,c,n). RAA

>
> According to you, however, if (2) is true (and I assume we all know
> that (2) was proved by Wiles), then (1) is meaningless.  Yet, no one
> here balked at the claim that (1) could be used to prove (2) (once (3)
> was proved).  No one here had any trouble understanding what (1)
> means.  Everyone in the thread accepted this form of mathematical
> argument as beyond suspicion -- although the claim that Simon actually
> proved (1) is regarded as doubtful.
>
> So, you're just plain wrong.  These statements that you call
> meaningless occur in ordinary mathematical reasoning all the time.  
>
> Footnotes:
> [1]  Message id
> <1917288606.455209.1269716329839.JavaMail.r...(a)gallium.mathforum.org>,
> in the thread "Another Proof of Fermats Last Theorem".
>
> [2]  Message id
> <50f09d88-a96b-464c-aec5-be000f0be...(a)x23g2000prd.googlegroups.com>.
>
> [3]  Message id
> <e6768d43-7706-41f4-bff8-8e666d693...(a)j21g2000yqh.googlegroups.com>.
>
> --
> "There's lots of things in this old world to take a poor boy down.
> If you leave them be, you can save yourself some pain.
> You don't have to live in fear, but you best have some respect,
> For rattlesnakes, painted ladies and cocaine."  -- Bob Childers

From: Newberry on
On Mar 30, 3:51 am, stevendaryl3...(a)yahoo.com (Daryl McCullough)
wrote:
> Newberry says...
>
> >There are two issues here.
> >a) The two tokens have the same subject and the same predicate.
> >b) The resolution can be seemingly defeated by forcing all tokens into
> >one type.
>
> >Not sure why you think they are related.
>
> Any theory of truth that is worth considering, if two sentence
> tokens have the same subject and same predicate, then they have
> the same truth value. Otherwise, your notion of truth is unconnected
> with the meaning of sentences.

Why are you stating this so categorically? Look at this excerpt from
Gaifman:

QUOTE
Line 1: The sentence on line 1 is not true.
Line 2: The sentence on line 1 is not true.

The standard evaluation rule for a sentence of the form ‘The sentence
written in/on ... is true’ is roughly this:
(*) Go to ... and evaluate the sentence written there. If that
sentence is true, so is ‘The sentence written in ... is true’ , else
the latter is false.
END OF QUOTE

If you apply this procedure to 1 it will never terminate, so neither T
nor F will be assigned to 1. If we apply the same procedure to 2,
knowing that 1 is ~(T v F) we obtain that 2 is true.

Another way to see this is that 1 is not expressing any possible state
of affairs. 2 is. It expresses the state of affairs that 1 does not
correspond to an actual state of affairs.

>
> >Let's take a) first. Gaifman's evaluation procedure is such that if
> >two tokens have the same subjects and predicates one can nevertheless
> >be true and the other neither true nor false.
>
> >Now b):
> >    This sentence is not truthy.
> >    "This sentence is not truthy" is not truthy.
>
> >These two sentences have the same subjects and predicates. The former
> >is self-referential the latter is not.
>
> Using Godel coding, you can eliminate direct self-reference and thereby
> make the two sentences identical. Then it is a contradiction to say that
> one is truthy and the other is not.
>
> --
> Daryl McCullough
> Ithaca, NY

From: Daryl McCullough on
Newberry says...
>
>On Mar 30, 3:51=A0am, stevendaryl3...(a)yahoo.com (Daryl McCullough)
>wrote:

>> Any theory of truth that is worth considering, if two sentence
>> tokens have the same subject and same predicate, then they have
>> the same truth value. Otherwise, your notion of truth is unconnected
>> with the meaning of sentences.
>
>Why are you stating this so categorically?

I'm just stating what truth *means. A sentence makes (or attempts to make)
a claim about something. To understand a sentence means to understand
what is being claimed, and about what.

Look at this excerpt from
>Gaifman:
>
>QUOTE
>Line 1: The sentence on line 1 is not true.
>Line 2: The sentence on line 1 is not true.

Yes, it's a silly notion of truth that gives these two sentences
different truth values.

>The standard evaluation rule for a sentence of the form "The sentence
>written in/on ... is true" is roughly this:
>(*) Go to ... and evaluate the sentence written there. If that
>sentence is true, so is "The sentence written in ... is true", else
>the latter is false.
>END OF QUOTE

To me, the truth of a sentence is determined by what it *says*, not
be the result of an evaluation procedure. Now, of course, you could
use an evaluation procedure to *define* a property of sentences.
That's what proof within a mathematical theory does. It's an evaluation
procedure for sentences. Sentences that pass the evaluation are called
"theorems". If you are proposing a more sophisticated evaluation procedure,
then you're extending the notion of "theorem". But you're not defining
truth.

>Another way to see this is that 1 is not expressing any possible state
>of affairs.

Sure it does. You are using the word "true" to mean "evaluates to true
after applying Gaifman's evaluation procedure". So the meaning of 1
is:

"The sentence on line 1 does not evaluate to true under Gaifman's
evaluation procedure"

That's a perfectly meaningful state of affairs, and it happens to be
the case.

--
Daryl McCullough
Ithaca, NY