From: Jesse F. Hughes on
Newberry <newberryxy(a)gmail.com> writes:

> On Feb 28, 3:54 pm, Aatu Koskensilta <aatu.koskensi...(a)uta.fi> wrote:
>> Newberry <newberr...(a)gmail.com> writes:
>> > b) Is this
>>
>> >     (x)((2 > x > 4) -> ~(x < x + 1))
>>
>> > "ordinary mathematical reasoning"?
>>
>> It isn't reasoning at all. It's a formula that doesn't formalize any
>> statement we would ordinarily meet in mathematical reasoning.
>
> So why do you exhort people that it is true?

It's not that sentence that we're interested in, but there are similar
sentences that *are* used in mathematical reasoning.

Suppose, for instance, that we have a proof

(Ex)Px -> (Ex)(Px & Qx).

For instance, let Px stand for (E a,b,c)(a^x + b^x = c^x) and Qx stand
for x is prime. Then we know that the above sentence is true: if
there is a counterexample to Fermat's last theorem, then there is a
counterexample in which the exponent is prime.

Equivalently,

~(Ex)(Px & Qx) -> ~(Ex)Px. (1)

Suppose further that I prove (according to the usual notion of
mathematical proof) that

~(Ex)(Px & Qx). (2)

Then, (1) and (2) allow me to conclude

~(Ex)Px. (3)

Ah, but here's the rub! According to your comments, if (3) is true,
then (2) is neither true nor false and hence not true. If (2) is not
true, then surely there is something wrong with my proof of (3), since
my proof of (3) depends on (2). I thought I had a proof of (2), but
it turns out that I didn't.

At this point, you may say that what I really had was a proof of a
second-order statement

~T((Ex)(Px & Qx)), (2')

and that I can somehow use (2') and (1) to derive (3), but you are
only blowing steam at present, since you haven't given us any
second-order logic to conclude that (1) & (2') |- (3).

Statements like (2) are useful in mathematical reasoning. We use them
to derive statements like (3).

--
"I told her that I loved her.
She said she loved me too.
Neither one was lying,
Yet it wasn't true." -- Del McCoury Band
From: Marshall on
On Mar 2, 6:30 am, "Jesse F. Hughes" <je...(a)phiwumbda.org> wrote:
> Newberry <newberr...(a)gmail.com> writes:
>
>
> At this point, you may say that what I really had was a proof of a
> second-order statement
>
>   ~T((Ex)(Px & Qx)),                    (2')
>
> and that I can somehow use (2') and (1) to derive (3), but you are
> only blowing steam at present, since you haven't given us any
> second-order logic to conclude that (1) & (2') |- (3).
>
> Statements like (2) are useful in mathematical reasoning.  We use them
> to derive statements like (3).

One thing that the cranks and crankophiles never understand
is that the systems they come up with add a lot of complexity
while actually removing functionality or utility. To do so
merely to avoid some counterintuitive but harmless
property (such as vacuous truth, in Newberry's case) is
a huge waste of time.

Less powerful; more work to use: that's a crank theory for you.


Marshall

PS. To the extent that you can call them "theories."
PPS. This post applies equally well in the current Easterly thread.
From: Newberry on
On Mar 2, 6:30 am, "Jesse F. Hughes" <je...(a)phiwumbda.org> wrote:
> Newberry <newberr...(a)gmail.com> writes:
> > On Feb 28, 3:54 pm, Aatu Koskensilta <aatu.koskensi...(a)uta.fi> wrote:
> >> Newberry <newberr...(a)gmail.com> writes:
> >> > b) Is this
>
> >> >     (x)((2 > x > 4) -> ~(x < x + 1))
>
> >> > "ordinary mathematical reasoning"?
>
> >> It isn't reasoning at all. It's a formula that doesn't formalize any
> >> statement we would ordinarily meet in mathematical reasoning.
>
> > So why do you exhort people that it is true?
>
> It's not that sentence that we're interested in, but there are similar
> sentences that *are* used in mathematical reasoning.
>
> Suppose, for instance, that we have a proof
>
>   (Ex)Px -> (Ex)(Px & Qx).
>
> For instance, let Px stand for (E a,b,c)(a^x + b^x = c^x) and Qx stand
> for x is prime.  Then we know that the above sentence is true: if
> there is a counterexample to Fermat's last theorem, then there is a
> counterexample in which the exponent is prime.
>
> Equivalently,
>
>   ~(Ex)(Px & Qx) -> ~(Ex)Px.            (1)
>
> Suppose further that I prove (according to the usual notion of
> mathematical proof) that
>
>   ~(Ex)(Px & Qx).                       (2)
>
> Then, (1) and (2) allow me to conclude
>
>   ~(Ex)Px.                              (3)
>
> Ah, but here's the rub!  According to your comments, if (3) is true,
> then (2) is neither true nor false and hence not true.  If (2) is not
> true, then surely there is something wrong with my proof of (3), since
> my proof of (3) depends on (2).  I thought I had a proof of (2), but
> it turns out that I didn't.
>
> At this point, you may say that what I really had was a proof of a
> second-order statement
>
>   ~T((Ex)(Px & Qx)),                    (2')
>
> and that I can somehow use (2') and (1) to derive (3), but you are
> only blowing steam at present, since you haven't given us any
> second-order logic to conclude that (1) & (2') |- (3).
>
> Statements like (2) are useful in mathematical reasoning.  We use them
> to derive statements like (3).
>
> --
> "I told her that I loved her.
>  She said she loved me too.
>  Neither one was lying,
>  Yet it wasn't true."                 -- Del McCoury Band

Was this selected at random?
From: Jesse F. Hughes on
Newberry <newberryxy(a)gmail.com> writes:

> On Mar 2, 6:30 am, "Jesse F. Hughes" <je...(a)phiwumbda.org> wrote:
>> Newberry <newberr...(a)gmail.com> writes:
>> > On Feb 28, 3:54 pm, Aatu Koskensilta <aatu.koskensi...(a)uta.fi> wrote:
>> >> Newberry <newberr...(a)gmail.com> writes:
>> >> > b) Is this
>>
>> >> >     (x)((2 > x > 4) -> ~(x < x + 1))
>>
>> >> > "ordinary mathematical reasoning"?
>>
>> >> It isn't reasoning at all. It's a formula that doesn't formalize any
>> >> statement we would ordinarily meet in mathematical reasoning.
>>
>> > So why do you exhort people that it is true?
>>
>> It's not that sentence that we're interested in, but there are similar
>> sentences that *are* used in mathematical reasoning.
>>
>> Suppose, for instance, that we have a proof
>>
>>   (Ex)Px -> (Ex)(Px & Qx).
>>
>> For instance, let Px stand for (E a,b,c)(a^x + b^x = c^x) and Qx stand
>> for x is prime.  Then we know that the above sentence is true: if
>> there is a counterexample to Fermat's last theorem, then there is a
>> counterexample in which the exponent is prime.
>>
>> Equivalently,
>>
>>   ~(Ex)(Px & Qx) -> ~(Ex)Px.            (1)
>>
>> Suppose further that I prove (according to the usual notion of
>> mathematical proof) that
>>
>>   ~(Ex)(Px & Qx).                       (2)
>>
>> Then, (1) and (2) allow me to conclude
>>
>>   ~(Ex)Px.                              (3)
>>
>> Ah, but here's the rub!  According to your comments, if (3) is true,
>> then (2) is neither true nor false and hence not true.  If (2) is not
>> true, then surely there is something wrong with my proof of (3), since
>> my proof of (3) depends on (2).  I thought I had a proof of (2), but
>> it turns out that I didn't.
>>
>> At this point, you may say that what I really had was a proof of a
>> second-order statement
>>
>>   ~T((Ex)(Px & Qx)),                    (2')
>>
>> and that I can somehow use (2') and (1) to derive (3), but you are
>> only blowing steam at present, since you haven't given us any
>> second-order logic to conclude that (1) & (2') |- (3).
>>
>> Statements like (2) are useful in mathematical reasoning.  We use them
>> to derive statements like (3).
>>
>> --
>> "I told her that I loved her.
>>  She said she loved me too.
>>  Neither one was lying,
>>  Yet it wasn't true."                 -- Del McCoury Band
>
> Was this selected at random?

Yes. Just another coincidence from the random number generator.

--
Jesse F. Hughes
"Students said they wanted to make people feel more comfortable by not
having to choose a gender at the bathroom door."
-- Boston Globe article on gender-neutral bathrooms at universities.
From: Jesse F. Hughes on
Newberry <newberryxy(a)gmail.com> writes:

> On Mar 2, 6:30 am, "Jesse F. Hughes" <je...(a)phiwumbda.org> wrote:
>> Suppose, for instance, that we have a proof
>>
>>   (Ex)Px -> (Ex)(Px & Qx).
>>
>> For instance, let Px stand for (E a,b,c)(a^x + b^x = c^x) and Qx stand
>> for x is prime.  Then we know that the above sentence is true: if
>> there is a counterexample to Fermat's last theorem, then there is a
>> counterexample in which the exponent is prime.
>>
>> Equivalently,
>>
>>   ~(Ex)(Px & Qx) -> ~(Ex)Px.            (1)
>>
>> Suppose further that I prove (according to the usual notion of
>> mathematical proof) that
>>
>>   ~(Ex)(Px & Qx).                       (2)
>>
>> Then, (1) and (2) allow me to conclude
>>
>>   ~(Ex)Px.                              (3)
>>
>> Ah, but here's the rub!  According to your comments, if (3) is true,
>> then (2) is neither true nor false and hence not true.  If (2) is not
>> true, then surely there is something wrong with my proof of (3), since
>> my proof of (3) depends on (2).  I thought I had a proof of (2), but
>> it turns out that I didn't.
>>
>> At this point, you may say that what I really had was a proof of a
>> second-order statement
>>
>>   ~T((Ex)(Px & Qx)),                    (2')
>>
>> and that I can somehow use (2') and (1) to derive (3), but you are
>> only blowing steam at present, since you haven't given us any
>> second-order logic to conclude that (1) & (2') |- (3).
>>
>> Statements like (2) are useful in mathematical reasoning.  We use them
>> to derive statements like (3)
>
> Obviously if we do not use clasical logic the derivation system will
> be different. If we have a semantically complete system and
>
> ~(Ex)Px. (3)
>
> is true then we will be able to prove it. Your example is useful when
> we use classical logic. If we do not then it will not be useful. It is
> that simple.

I just don't see any reason to give up a perfectly straightforward and
sensible argument (like that above) in order to fit your intuitions
that, if (3) is true, then (2) is neither true nor false. Perhaps
t-relevance logic is useful, but it does not seem to be satisfactory
for mathematical reasoning. In mathematics, the argument I outlined
above is a perfectly good argument for (3).

Seems to me that you've got quite a job convincing mathematicians
otherwise.

--
Jesse F. Hughes
"I'm a geek hatchling." -- Quincy P. Hughes, age 7