From: Sylvia Else on
On 23/06/2010 10:40 PM, WM wrote:
> On 23 Jun., 13:54, Sylvia Else<syl...(a)not.here.invalid> wrote:
>> On 23/06/2010 8:34 PM, WM wrote:
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>> On 23 Jun., 04:18, Sylvia Else<syl...(a)not.here.invalid> wrote:
>>>> On 23/06/2010 11:33 AM, Sylvia Else wrote:
>>
>>>>> On 23/06/2010 11:03 AM, Virgil wrote:
>>>>>> In article
>>>>>> <2000e81b-7c5a-41be-b6af-98f96f2fb...(a)w31g2000yqb.googlegroups.com>,
>>>>>> WM<mueck...(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de> wrote:
>>
>>>>>>> On 22 Jun., 21:34, Virgil<Vir...(a)home.esc> wrote:
>>
>>>>>>>>>> But (A0, A1, A2, ...) is obviously countable. Above you say it's
>>>>>>>>>> "certainly
>>>>>>>>>> not countable", but it is.
>>
>>>>>>>>> The set is certainly countable. But it cannot be written as a list
>>
>>>>>>>> But it HAS been written as a list (A0, A1, A2, ...),
>>
>>>>>>> Does this list contain the anti-diagonal of (..., An, ... A2, A1, A0,
>>>>>>> L0)?
>>
>>>>>> Since (..., An, ... A2, A1, A0, L0) does not appear to be a list, why
>>>>>> should there be any antidiagonal for it?
>>
>>>>> Ach! Let's scrap A0 - it's confusing.
>>
>>>>> If we let L_n be the nth element in the list L0, and An the
>>>>> anti-diagonal of the An-1, An-2,...., A1, L_1, L_2, L_3,...
>>
>>>>> then
>>
>>>>> L_1
>>>>> A1
>>>>> L_2
>>>>> A2
>>>>> L_3
>>>>> A3
>>>>> L_4
>>>>> ...
>>
>>>>> is a list. I'm still thinking about that.
>>
>>>>> Sylvia.
>>
>>>> Hmm...
>>
>>>> A1 is the antidiagonal of L1 L2 L3...
>>
>>>> A2 is the antidiagonal of L1 A1 L2 L3...
>>
>>>> A3 is the antidiagonal of L1 A1 L2 A2 L3 L4...
>>
>>>> Each An is thus constructed from a list that is different from the list
>>>> into which it is inserted. So the construction does not lead to a list
>>>> that should contain its own anti-diagonal, and it doesn't.
>>
>>> Ln =
>>
>>> An
>>> ...
>>> A2
>>> A1
>>> A0
>>> L0
>>
>>> Does your bijection contain the anti-diagonal of
>>> (..., An, ... A2, A1, A0, L0)?
>>
>> I don't understand why you've recast it back to that form.
>
> That is a an abbreviation of the construction I proposed. Of course
> the "..." stand only for an infinite sequence of well defined digits
> at finite places.
>
>> You can't
>> even form the anti-diagonal of that - what would the first digit of the
>> antidiagonal be?
>
> What would the last digit of a normal Cantor-diagonal? Why should the
> first digit be more important than the last one? An infinite sequence
> of digits (that is not converging and not defined by a finite formula,
> like Cantor's diagonal sequence) is as undefined when the last digit
> is missing as it is when the first digit is missing.

Cantor doesn't rely on being able to identify a last digit. He's just
saying that no matter how far down the list you look, you'll find that
the element at that point doesn't match the anti-diagonal. But you can't
even begin to formulate his proof if you can't identify the first
element of the list (and hence first digit of the anti-diagonal) either.

First and last are interchangeable, of course, but with your
construction above, you can't specify either the first or the last.

Sylvia.
From: Aatu Koskensilta on
Tim Little <tim(a)little-possums.net> writes:

> In fact it would be a lot easier if instead of reals, we talked about
> sets of natural numbers, and instead of computable reals, we talked
> about recursively enumerable sets of natural numbers.

It would be even more easy if instead of the uncountability of the reals
we talked about the standard proof of Cantor's theorem:

Let f be a function taking elements of a set A to subsets of A. There
is then a subset of A not in the range of f. For consider the set

D = {x in A | x not in f(x)}.

There is no a in A such that f(a) = D: if there were, we'd have a in
f(a) iff a not in f(a), a contradiction.

--
Aatu Koskensilta (aatu.koskensilta(a)uta.fi)

"Wovon man nicht sprechan kann, dar�ber muss man schweigen"
- Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
From: WM on
On 23 Jun., 14:51, Sylvia Else <syl...(a)not.here.invalid> wrote:

> Cantor doesn't rely on being able to identify a last digit. He's just
> saying that no matter how far down the list you look, you'll find that
> the element at that point doesn't match the anti-diagonal.


That is wrong. Cantor uses the alleged "fact", that infinity can be
completed, i.e., that that the infinite list can be finished.
If he would only assume what you say, then the anti-diagonal could
remain in the unknown part of the list. You know and appreciate that
after *any* line number n there are infinitely many more lines?

> But you can't
> even begin to formulate his proof if you can't identify the first
> element of the list (and hence first digit of the anti-diagonal) either.

Isn't it enough, also in my case, to know that every antidiagonal has
a first digit? In fact it has. Every antidiagonal is constructed from
a list with a first line (that is the previous antidiagonal) and the
remaining list. Every line has a finite number n.
>
> First and last are interchangeable, of course, but with your
> construction above, you can't specify either the first or the last.

As I told you, my notation is only an abbreviation for the following
definition:
1) Take a list L0 of all rational numbers.
2) Construct its antidiagonal A0.
3) Add it at position 0 to get (A0,L0)
4) Construct the antidiagonal A1.
5) and so on.

There occurs never a problem, because we know Hilberts hotel, don't
we?

Regards, WM
From: WM on
On 23 Jun., 14:57, Aatu Koskensilta <aatu.koskensi...(a)uta.fi> wrote:
> Tim Little <t...(a)little-possums.net> writes:
> > In fact it would be a lot easier if instead of reals, we talked about
> > sets of natural numbers, and instead of computable reals, we talked
> > about recursively enumerable sets of natural numbers.
>
> It would be even more easy if instead of the uncountability of the reals
> we talked about the standard proof of Cantor's theorem:
>
>  Let f be a function taking elements of a set A to subsets of A. There
>  is then a subset of A not in the range of f. For consider the set
>
>    D = {x in A | x not in f(x)}.
>
>  There is no a in A such that f(a) = D: if there were, we'd have a in
>  f(a) iff a not in f(a), a contradiction.

That could be a good proof, if we knew that all subsets of an infinite
set A would exist. But already Fraenkel wrote in the third edition of
his famous book (1928, p. 279f) with respect to the axiom of power
set, that: der Begriff "Teilmenge“ eine andere, wesentlich engere
Bedeutung hat als in der CANTORschen Mengenlehre. In dieser konnten
wir bei der Bildung der Potenzmenge Um eine beliebige Gesamtheit von
Elementen aus m zu einer Teilmenge von m zusammenfassen und waren dann
sicher, daß diese sich unter den Elementen von Um findet. Jetzt ist
uns eine derartige, weitgehende Freiheit gewährende "Bildung“ einer
Teilmenge von m nicht gestattet, also auch ihr Auftreten unter den
Elementen von Um keineswegs gesichert. (Contrary to the second edition
of 1923, Fraenkel now knew Skolem's proof of the same year and had to
explain how it could be circumvented.)

Therefore, there is not every subset of an infinite set. Why then
should exist the subset of A that contains its pre-image if it does
not contain it, and does not contain ist, if it contains it?

With no doubt this is a curious result of logic, but it has not the
least to do with cardinalities of sets.

Regards, WM
From: Aatu Koskensilta on
WM <mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de> writes:

> Therefore, there is not every subset of an infinite set.

What on Earth does this mean?

--
Aatu Koskensilta (aatu.koskensilta(a)uta.fi)

"Wovon man nicht sprechan kann, dar�ber muss man schweigen"
- Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus