From: Jesse F. Hughes on
Newberry <newberryxy(a)gmail.com> writes:

>> Because every infinite sequence of digits represents a real number?  And
>> the antidiagonal is one such sequence?
>
> If it does not exist then it does not represent anything let alone a
> number.
>
> Now it is clear that it does not exist. Since all the reals are on the
> list and the anti-diagonal would differ from any of them. This
> violates the assumption. Hence the anti-diagonal does not exist.

Wow. Are you saying that the *sequence of digits* specified by the
anti-diagonal does not exist?

Anyway, in a sense, you're right. If we assume that every real is
represented by a sequence on the list, then we can prove that every
sequence occurs on the list (ignoring the issue of multiple
representations). And yet, we can also show that a particular sequence
is not on the list. This is a contradiction and hence *our assumption*
that every real is represented by a sequence on the list must be false.

You've never seen proof by contradiction in your life? How remarkable.

--
Jesse F. Hughes

"Of course, I don't need any more education."
-- Quincy P. Hughes (age 7)
From: stevendaryl3016 on
Peter Webb says...

>Well, there are lots of definitions of a computable Real, I will use
>Wikipedia's most intuitive definition: "computable reals, are the real
>numbers that can be computed to within any desired precision by a finite,
>terminating algorithm."

That's too loose. It should be a an algorithm with *one* argument,
the degree of precision required. An algorithm with two arguments
doesn't count.

You can define an algorithm that takes two arguments,
a list of computable reals, and a natural n, which
returns a computable real that is not on the list.
But that real is not necessarily computable by an
algorithm that only has one argument.

>1. Given a list of computable Reals, we can identify the nth
>computable Real on the list by simply counting down to the nth entry.
>
>2. Given the nth computable Real on the list, we can count off and identify
>the nth digit of this Real.
>
>3. With the nth digit of the Real, we can use Cantor's construction to
>identify the nth digit of the anti-diagonal.
>
>4. As we can specify every digit in the anti-diagonal explicitly and to any
>desired degree of accuracy, it is therefore computable.

You've described a computable function of *two* arguments:
(1) the list, and (2) a natural n. For the antidiagonal to
be computable, you must show that there is an algorithm
that only takes one argument, a natural number n, and returns
the nth decimal place of the antidiagonal.

>5. But the anti-diagonal number does not appear on the list.
>
>6. Therefore, the list could not have included all computable Reals.
>
>Exactly the same as Cantor's proof that the Reals cannot be listed.

The difference is that the antidiagonal of a list of reals returns
a real that is not on the list. The antidiagonal of a list of
computable reals does *not* necessarily return a computable real.

>The only difference is that I have to prove that the anti-diagonal
>is also computable

which you haven't done. To prove that it is computable, you
have to have an algorithm that takes one argument, n, and
returns the nth decimal place of the real. You haven't shown
that there is such an algorithm. You've shown that there is
an algorithm that takes two arguments and produces the nth
decimal place.

>but because Cantor's proof explicitly constructs the
>anti-diagonal it is clearly computable

It's a computable function of *two* arguments. That doesn't
mean that there is a computable function of *one* argument.

--
Daryl McCullough
Ithaca, NY

From: WM on
On 19 Jun., 15:31, stevendaryl3...(a)yahoo.com (Daryl McCullough( wrote:
> Peter Webb says...
>
> >but because Cantor's proof explicitly constructs the
> >anti-diagonal it is clearly computable
>
> It's a computable function of *two* arguments. That doesn't
> mean that there is a computable function of *one* argument.


What a ridiculous discussion!

Whatever Cantor's argument produces, it is something more or less
definite. But everything that is definite enough to be distinguished
from every other real number belongs to a countabe set. And everything
less definite cannot be distinguished from other less definite objects
and is certainly not a number.

Cantor's "proof" shows either that a countabke set is uncountable or
that a number that can be distinguished from every other number cannot
be distinguished from every other number.

It is a pity that you were told that many years ago and have not yet
understood it!

Regards, WM
From: WM on
On 19 Jun., 15:06, stevendaryl3...(a)yahoo.com (Daryl McCullough( wrote:
> Peter Webb says...
>
> >I agree that computable reals are countable. But I do not agree this means
> >they can be listed. In fact, I can easily prove they are not. If you give me
> >a purported list of all computable Reals I can use a diagonal argument to
> >form a computable Real not on the list.
>
> You can use a diagonal argument to form a *real* that is not on the list.
> For that real to be *computable*, you need to show that you can compute
> that real *without* using the list.
>
> If the list were a computable list, then you could reconstruct it yourself,
> so the antidiagonal would be computable. If the list is not computable,
> then neither is the antidiagonal.

All finite definitions of numbers map on infinite sequences of digits.
But infinite sequences of digits do not map on finite definitions.

It is not possible to define a number by an infinite sequence of
digits without having the finite definition.

Cantor's list consists of infinite sequences of digits. They are not
defined and they do not define anything.

Only finite definitions define numbers. But an infinite list of finite
definitions cannot be diagonalized.

Reagrsd, WM
From: WM on
On 19 Jun., 05:10, Virgil <Vir...(a)home.esc> wrote:
> In article

> > It is. Every real number that is defined is defined by a finite word
> > (definition or formula). It is impossible to define a number by an
> > infinite sequence, because the sequence never ends and the definition
> > is never known.
>
> F:N -> R: n -> 3/10^n is an infinite sequence defining a real number.

No, "F:N -> R: n -> 3/10^n" is a finite rule *producing* an infinite
sequence!
>
> So as one can easily see it is possible to have an infinite sequence
> defining a real number.
>
> In real mathematics, an infinite sequence is merely a function whose
> domain is the set of natural numbers, and there are lots of them which
> define real numbers.

There is none. But you are not able to grasp the difference between an
infinite sequence and the rule producing that sequence.

Sorry, but if you cannot think so far, then further discussion is
meaningless.

Regards, WM