From: Daryl McCullough on
julio(a)diegidio.name says...
>Shall I point you too to some article on the diagonal argument?

Uh, *your* the one who doesn't understand it. So people should
be pointing *you* to relevant articles. For example:

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cantor%27s_diagonal_argument
http://mathworld.wolfram.com/CantorDiagonalMethod.html
http://www.mathpages.com/home/kmath371.htm

Cantor also gave, before his diagonal proof, an alternative
proof of the uncountability of the reals:

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cantor%27s_first_uncountability_proof

--
Daryl McCullough
Ithaca, NY

From: jacko on
On 8 Aug, 10:09, RichD <r_delaney2...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
> I heard someone say recently, "The proof of the Turing
> machine halting problem is an example of diagonalization."

I'm sure i saw a 'proof'' using the set of all programs example..

> I don't see that.  As I recall, it's proof by contradiction;
> assume a program which accomplishes the goal, feed
> the code of this program to itself, etc., ad absurdum.  QED
>
> Whereas diagonalization consists of constructing a list,
> then constructing a new object not in the list, etc.

This is very logically flawed, because the thing constructed i the
next element of such a lst, therefore it is always possible to
construct something extra which is in the list, as well as show
something is not in the list yet.

order of reals is same as rationals :i.e. z^2.

proof: place all Zintegers in a list. do this again. Then place a
mirror with a little black spot point in fromt of one set.
Now all reals are the sum f an element from one list and an element
from the other. Z*Z = Z^2.

Now this is obvoius, and requires no proof by negation, so the flaws
of such negation proofs discovered via godel can not be seen in it.

In relation to turing halting. I can say no more than DO'T use
diagonalization and proof by negation if there are oher options.

cheers
jacko
From: jacko on
nd just for the record pi is an infinite rational.

proof: cos pi is defined as an infinite summation of rationals.
summing rationals ALWAYS produces a rational.

From: Ben Bacarisse on
julio(a)diegidio.name writes:
<snip>
> With my construction I don't get higher order infinite ordinals, but
> instead I get that 'oo' is representable, as is 'oo-1' and so on. That
> is, we can enumerate from zero as well as enumerate back from
> infinity. And I mean we can enumerate forwards or backwards the
> infinite list of the computable reals, say in [0, 1], where 1 is the
> usual diagonal at 0 and viceversa, 0 is the inverse diagonal at 1.
> Actually, given an ordering rule over the list, we can enumerate
> forwards or backwards at some specific points, but I'll leave the
> details out.

So order the list of "computable reals" in [0, 1] (I use quotes
because I am quoting you -- I don't know what these things are yet) to
get r1, r2, r3... and consider the list of numbers r(n):

r1+(r2-r1)/2, r1+(r2-r1)/3, r1+(r2-r1)/4,... r1+(r2-r1)/(n+1),...

All of these look computable to me so this list is simply a
permutation of r1, r2, r3... Which one is equal to r1 and which one
is equal to r2? What follows from r(x) = r1 and/or r(y) = r2?

--
Ben.
From: cplxphil on


> nd just for the record pi is an infinite rational.
>
> proof: cos pi is defined as an infinite summation of rationals.
> summing rationals ALWAYS produces a rational.


Pi is irrational. A finite sum of rationals is rational, but an
infinite sum need not be. How would you express pi as the quotient of
two integers (the definition of a rational)?