From: Aatu Koskensilta on 31 Jul 2010 07:02 David R Tribble <david(a)tribble.com> writes: > That was my feeling, but is there a specific line of argument > about how we know that? Is there a particular property (or lack > of one) of Cs that renders it a class? For any x, there's a definable (with x as a parameter) bijection between Cs(x) and the totality of all sets. By replacement, it follows that Cs(x) can't be a set. David Hartley already outlined an explicit definition of a suitable bijection: just take the set y to {x,y}. -- Aatu Koskensilta (aatu.koskensilta(a)uta.fi) "Wovon man nicht sprechen kann, dar�ber muss man schweigen" - Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
From: Aatu Koskensilta on 31 Jul 2010 07:12 David R Tribble <david(a)tribble.com> writes: > I meant a universe of sets of a finite size, e.g., the universe of > sets having no more than three members. Perhaps this is a specific > kind of "model"? I take it you have in mind something like the least fixed point S_n of the operation P_n(X) = X union {A subset X | A is of cardinality <= n} for a given n. This is just the familiar cumulative hierarchy with sets of cardinality > n dropped -- we obtain S_n as the limit of the sequence S_n(0) = the empty set S_n(i+1) = P_n(S_n(i)) = S_n(i) union {A subset S_n(i) | card(A) <= n} by setting S_n = union of S_n(i) for i in omega. There are infinitely many sets in S_n for n > 0, since {} is in S_n and {{}}, {{{}}}, and so on are all one element sets. In S_1 there is, for any set A in S_1, only one set having A as an element, namely {A}, so the set having this set as its element is the collection of all sets (in S_1) having A as an element, and is in S_1. For n > 1 the collection of all sets in S_n having a given set A in S_n as an element is infinite, since there are infinitely many sets in S_n, and for any set X in S_n, {A,X} is a set in S_n having A as an element. So the set of all sets containing A as an element, not being of cardinality <= n, is not in S_n when n > 1. -- Aatu Koskensilta (aatu.koskensilta(a)uta.fi) "Wovon man nicht sprechen kann, dar�ber muss man schweigen" - Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
From: Butch Malahide on 31 Jul 2010 20:22 On Jul 31, 6:02 am, Aatu Koskensilta <aatu.koskensi...(a)uta.fi> wrote: > David R Tribble <da...(a)tribble.com> writes: > > > That was my feeling, but is there a specific line of argument > > about how we know that? Is there a particular property (or lack > > of one) of Cs that renders it a class? > > For any x, there's a definable (with x as a parameter) bijection between > Cs(x) and the totality of all sets. By replacement, it follows that > Cs(x) can't be a set. David Hartley already outlined an explicit > definition of a suitable bijection: just take the set y to {x,y}. Maybe you need replacement to prove that Cs(x) is not a set for any possible choice of x. However, unless x is something very exotic, you can get by with just separation, pairing, and union. Namely, if Cs(x) is a set, then consider the set R = {x} union {A in CS(x)| A not in A}. Since the assumption "R not in R" leads to a contradiction, we must have R in R, and in fact R = x; i.e., x = {x} union {A| x in A and A not in A}.
From: Butch Malahide on 31 Jul 2010 20:25 On Jul 31, 7:22 pm, Butch Malahide <fred.gal...(a)gmail.com> wrote: > On Jul 31, 6:02 am, Aatu Koskensilta <aatu.koskensi...(a)uta.fi> wrote: > > > David R Tribble <da...(a)tribble.com> writes: > > > > That was my feeling, but is there a specific line of argument > > > about how we know that? Is there a particular property (or lack > > > of one) of Cs that renders it a class? > > > For any x, there's a definable (with x as a parameter) bijection between > > Cs(x) and the totality of all sets. By replacement, it follows that > > Cs(x) can't be a set. David Hartley already outlined an explicit > > definition of a suitable bijection: just take the set y to {x,y}. Maybe you need replacement to prove that Cs(x) is not a set for any possible choice of x. However, unless x is something very exotic, you can get by with just separation, pairing, and union. Namely, if Cs(x) is a set, then consider the set R = {x} union {A in Cs(x) | A not in A}. Since the assumption "R not in R" leads to a contradiction, we must have R in R, and in fact R = x; i.e., x = {x} union {A | x in A and A not in A}.
From: David R Tribble on 1 Aug 2010 16:09 David R Tribble writes: >> That was my feeling, but is there a specific line of argument >> about how we know that? Is there a particular property (or lack >> of one) of Cs that renders it a class? > Aatu Koskensilta wrote: >> For any x, there's a definable (with x as a parameter) bijection between >> Cs(x) and the totality of all sets. By replacement, it follows that >> Cs(x) can't be a set. David Hartley already outlined an explicit >> definition of a suitable bijection: just take the set y to {x,y}. > Butch Malahide wrote: > Maybe you need replacement to prove that Cs(x) is not a set for any > possible choice of x. However, unless x is something very exotic, you > can get by with just separation, pairing, and union. Namely, if Cs(x) > is a set, then consider the set > R = {x} union {A in CS(x)| A not in A}. > Since the assumption "R not in R" leads to a contradiction, we must > have R in R, and in fact R = x; i.e., > x = {x} union {A| x in A and A not in A}. I expected Russel's paradox to be at play somewhere in there. I didn't know where to start, though, not being an expert.
First
|
Prev
|
Next
|
Last
Pages: 1 2 3 Prev: u^6 + v^6 + w^6 + x^6 + y^6 = z^6 Next: Obscure theorem: panic. |