From: Tim Little on
On 2010-08-05, jkcender <jkcmsal(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
> On Aug 4, 7:26pm, Tim Little <t...(a)little-possums.net> wrote:
>> 1 + ((-1) + z)
>> = 1 + (-1) ... by (3)
>> = z ... by (4).

You haven't addressed this derivation. Which step is incorrect? It
should be easy, there are only two and I've labelled both of them with
the numbering of rules you provided.


> 1 + (-1)= z therefore 1 + (-1) + z = 1z + 1z = 2z also 1 + ((-1) +
> z) = (1 + (-1)) + z = 2z
> Associativity holds.

You're assuming that associativity holds to show that associativity
holds. If you're stating that associativity holds as an *axiom*, you
should say so and accept that your system is then inconsistent.


- Tim
From: Tim Little on
On 2010-08-05, jkcender <jkcmsal(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
> rewritten with all zero numbers we can see that it does not equal z.
> 1z^0 + ((-1z^0) + z^1) =/= z. I hope it is clear here that, just like
> in any polynomial, terms with different powers cannot be added.

So your rule (3) is actually false? It is not true that x + nz = x?


- Tim
From: Tim Little on
On 2010-08-05, jkcender <jkcmsal(a)yahoo.com> wrote:

> The associative property fails here in the same way that the
> associative property of addition fails when adding Reals and
> imaginaries.

The associative property of addition works perfectly well when adding
reals and imaginaries. The difference is that nobody working in
complex arithmetic claims that imaginaries are additive identities for
reals.


- Tim
From: Transfer Principle on
On Aug 5, 5:13 pm, jkcender <jkcm...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
> On Aug 5, 12:33 pm, Transfer Principle <lwal...(a)lausd.net> wrote:
> > I point out that there is a similar trick to make Tim Golden's polysigned
> > numbers work, so we may try the same thing here.
> I am not familiar with Tim Golden's polysigned numbers work. Having
> said that I will point out a couple of possible problems with the
> following as applies to the new zero numbers based upon my
> understanding of the symbols used here. My apologies if there is some
> intricacy of Golden's of which I'm unaware.

I apologize for being a bit confusing here. I refer to
several concepts in this post, so let me address them
one at a time.

First of all, Cender, are you familiar with the
standard construction of the set R of real numbers via
Cauchy sequences or Dedekind cuts? Posters like Little
and Tonio definitely are familiar with these, and so
it might helpful to know about this when discussing
the z-numbers with them. Basically, what I'm trying to
do here is proceed with the usual construction, but as
soon as the number 0 appears, replace it with the new
number z.

Typically, one starts with the natural numbers N, then
the integers Z, forms the rational numbers Q, and
finally the real numbers R. The step from Z to Q is
probably the step that is best-known. We start with
fractions, which are pairs of integers -- for example,
one-half is 1/2. Then we have equivalence classes of
fractions, where some fractions are declared to be
equivalent, such as 1/2 and 2/4. The rule (equivalence
relation) which determines whether two fractions are
equivalent is as follows: a/b = c/d iff ad = bc. Then
we add rules for how to multiply, add, and compare two
fractions, and voila! We have the set Q of rationals.

Where do rationals come from? They come from _dividing_
two integers, since it was realized that some division
problems, such as 1 divided by 2, are impossible unless
we have fractions. Similarly, integers come from
_subtracting_ two naturals, since it was realized that
some subtraction problems, such as 1-2, are impossible
unless we have negative integers.

And so the construction from N to Z is similar to that
from Z to Q, except now we have ordered pairs of
naturals that we're trying to subtract, not divide. So
just as a/b means a divided by b, at this step of the
construction, (a,b) means a-b. Similarly, we have
equivalence classes of these ordered pairs, except that
the equivalence relation is now that (a,b) = (c,d) iff
we have a+d = b+c.

Thus (2,1), (3,2), (4,3), and so on are equivalent. All
of these equal the integer +1. Similarly, (1,2), (2,3),
(3,4), and so on equal the integer -1. But what about
the ordered pair (1,1)? Aha -- this is exactly where
the number 0 first appears in our construction, and
this is exactly where we want to take 0 out and put our
z in. The key to constructing Cender's system therefore
is to avoid 1-1 = 0 and have 1-1 = z instead.

But 0 appears fairly early in our construction from N
to Z to Q to R. What I'd like to do is go as far as we
can before worrying about 0. As it turns out, the poster
David Ullrich recently posted how we can go from N to
the _positive_ rationals Q+ and the _positive_ reals R+
without worrying about zero. The positive reals work
exactly the same in both R+ and Cender's system. And so
we can use R+ as a starting point. (Try a Google search
for David Ullrich algebra question in 2010 for more
information on the construction from N to R+.)

> > Indeed, the polynomial 0 is allowed -- (P,0) is a polynomial with all positive
> > coefficients, and (0,P) is a polynomial with all negative coefficients.
> So what happens in Golden's system when we substitute z for 0 in the
> above? For example, (P,nz) is a polynomial with all positive
> coefficients, and (nz,P) is a polynomial with all negative
> coefficients? As best I understand, I agree with this. Again, barring
> some intricacy of Golden's of which I'm unaware.

Ah, Golden's system. As I wrote earlier, the key to
constructing Cender's system is avoiding 1-1 = 0. As it
turns out, Golden wants to avoid 1-1 = 0 as well, but
in a different manner. In Golden's system, instead of
having a positive and negative number combine to give
zero, he wants to have a third sign, *, in addition to
the two standard signs - and +. Then one has to combine
all three signs to obtain zero, as in -1+1*1 = 0. To
construct the polysigned numbers, we use equivalence
classes of ordered _triples_, so that (1,1,1) = 0. To
learn more about polysigned numbers, one can refer to
the following link:

http://www.bandtechnology.com/PolySigned/PolySigned.html

Leaving Golden's numbers aside, let's begin the
construction of Cender's numbers from R+.

As Cender points out, many of his numbers can be written
as a polynomial in z. Because of this, we start out by
consider the set R+[z] of polynomials in z with positive
real coefficients.

Now -- and this is where I confused Cender earlier -- we
notice that in a polynomial such as 4z+5z^3, there is no
z^2 term. The z^2 term is _missing_. Indeed, so are the
constant, z^4 term, z^5 term, etc. -- in fact, every
polynomial must have all but finitely many terms missing.

And so, R+[z] must contain a polynomial such that _every_
term is missing. In standard theory, we would normally
refer to this as the "zero polynomial," but in Cender's
theory, there is no 0. So let's instead call it the
"vanishing" polynomial.

But what about negative coefficients, since after all, the
coefficients of the polys come from R+? Let's go back to
the construction of Z from N, where we had ordered pairs
such as (1,2) to denote -1. In a way, the first natural
in the ordered pair means +1, and the second natural in
the ordered pair means -2, and +1-2 = -1.

And so (4z,5z^3) denotes 4z-5z^3.

But what if all the coefficients have the same sign? This
is where the vanishing poly comes in. We have that
(4z+5z^3,vanishing) denotes 4z+5z^3, while if we want
-4z-5z^3, we use (vanishing,4z+5z^3). But what we can't
have is (vanishing,vanishing) -- because this would
correspond to traditional 0, which doesn't exist.

And so we have the set of all ordered pairs of polys in
z, with positive coefficients, such that at least one of
the polys doesn't vanish. It is the Cartesian product of
R+[z] with itself, with one element missing.

All we need now is an equivalence relation which tells us
which expressions are equal. For example, we want to make
the pair (1,1) equivalent to (z,vanishing), since this
tells us that 1-1 = z, the fundamental equation.

This is difficult. I will need some more time to think
about this for a while. But thank you, Cender, for
providing us with such an interesting system!
From: Jonathan Cender on
On Aug 6, 5:18 pm, Tim Little <t...(a)little-possums.net> wrote:
> On 2010-08-05, jkcender <jkcm...(a)yahoo.com> wrote:
>
> > On Aug 4, 7:26pm, Tim Little <t...(a)little-possums.net> wrote:
> >> 1 + ((-1) + z)
> >> = 1 + (-1) ... by (3)
> >> = z ... by (4).
>
> You haven't addressed this derivation.  Which step is incorrect?  It
> should be easy, there are only two and I've labelled both of them with
> the numbering of rules you provided.

Tim, First let me say I appreciate your patience and the time you’ve
spent on thinking about this. Your questions are helping me examine
basic assumptions that in some cases I haven’t even known I’ve made
about the consequences of changing the Peano axioms in this way. I’m
quite excited by your questions because, if this alternate arithmetic
is to be useful, they need a good answer.

Specifically about the above, I now understand what you meant. The
ellipses threw me and I jumped to the wrong conclusion and answered a
question you didn’t actually ask.

Here’s my attempt to answer. Reals and zero numbers are not
associative as I’ve said before. So parentheses matter. As long as
those parentheses are there, z is the answer, not 2z. To repeat, what
you have written above is correct. It is equal to z by 4 and 5 if (-1)
+ z is not in final form. The z just drops off. Simple. But if the
parentheses change the answer changes; in this case to 2z.
What you may have teased out here is that it is possible to have more
than one arithmetic with the new zero. Rule 4 mushes too many things
together. Let’s separate them out.
Rule 4a. Additive identity. x + nz = x.
Rule 4b. x + nz is in final form

Rule 4a would be for one arithmetic and 4b for a separate one. 4b
would be a lot more complicated and harder to show whether it would
work or not. At least for me right now. Before looking just at rule 4a
math remember that

Rule 5, since it is not commutative as Transfer Principle showed at
the end of his first post, is now
n-n= nz and –(n-n)= -nz

OK, for arithmetic with just rule 4a, I’ve begun to wonder if
separating it out like this is a key to a number of issues I’ve
struggled with. By following the steps you have questioned, nz and –nz
can always be reduced to z and –z because nz = z + (n-1)z. Then set z
= 1 + (-1) as you’ve done and apply rules 4a and 5 again. Then the
need for rule 6 goes away as long as a suitable order of operations is
set up. [Rule 6 was there mainly to resolve one of the less common
reasons for the lack of definition for division by zero anyway. But
this resolves it, too.]

The result of this is that z is a lot more like 0 except that division
is defined for z. For example, Rule 2 just becomes Zero times any Real
number is z.
x * nz = xnz = z

Looking forward to your reply, especially if there's something I'm
overlooking. Jonathan
>
> > 1 + (-1)= z  therefore 1 + (-1) + z = 1z + 1z = 2z  also 1 + ((-1) +
> > z) = (1 + (-1)) + z = 2z
> > Associativity holds.
>
> You're assuming that associativity holds to show that associativity
> holds.  If you're stating that associativity holds as an *axiom*, you
> should say so and accept that your system is then inconsistent.
>
> - Tim

I hope the above response in this post also answers this part.
Associativity doesn’t hold. Let me know if there’s something still not
clear or I’m missing something.

- Jonathan