From: LauLuna on
On Nov 27, 12:32 am, LauLuna <laureanol...(a)yahoo.es> wrote:
> On Nov 25, 10:07 pm, "Mike Terry"
>
>
>
>
>
> <news.dead.person.sto...(a)darjeeling.plus.com> wrote:
> >  "LauLuna" <laureanol...(a)yahoo.es> wrote in message
>
> >news:36cb4819-04fd-4dbe-b204-7168ae550e23(a)p8g2000yqb.googlegroups.com...
>
> > > On Nov 23, 12:22 pm, Herman Jurjus <hjm...(a)hetnet.nl> wrote:
> > > > Has anyone seen this before?
>
> > > >http://possiblyphilosophy.wordpress.com/2008/09/22/guessing-the-resul...
>
> > > > I'm not sure yet what to conclude from it; that AC is horribly wrong, or
> > > > that WM is horribly right, or something else altogether.
>
> > > > In short the story goes like this:
>
> > > > A game is played, in which infinitely many coins are tossed, and there's
> > > > one player, who makes infinitely many guesses. Both are done over a
> > > > finite period of time. The tosses and guesses are not made faster and
> > > > faster, however, but slower and slower: at t = 1/n. There's no 'first'
> > > > move.
>
> > > > Claim:
> > > > There exists a strategy with which you're certain to guess all entries
> > > > correctly except for at most finitely many mistakes. Not 'certain' as in
> > > > 'probability is 100%', but absolutely certain.
>
> > > > Reasoning:
> > > > On 2^w, consider the equivalence relation that makes x equivalent to y
> > > > when x(n) =/= y(n) for at most finitely many n. Next, using AC, create a
> > > > set S that contains precisely one element from every equivalence class.
> > > > Strategy: at every move, you already know the results of the previous
> > > > tosses, which is an infinite tail of some sequence in 2^w. Now take the
> > > > unique element from S associated to that tail, take the n'th element of
> > > > that sequence from S, and deliver that as your move.
> > > > After some thinking, you will see that with this strategy, you're indeed
> > > > certain to guess wrong at most finitely many times.
>
> > > > Thanks, AC! Another nice mess you've gotten us into.
>
> > > > --
> > > > Cheers,
> > > > Herman Jurjus
>
> > > In fact, you don't need the axiom of choice.
>
> > > At any 1/n hour past 12pm it is already determinate what equivalence
> > > class the eventual sequence is in. Since you know what the previous
> > > results are and there are only finitely many outstanding results, you
> > > can complete the sequence at random and take it as your
> > > representative. Which means that from any 1/n hr past 12pm on you can
> > > guess at random.
>
> > ..but then how would you prove that there have been only a finite number of
> > incorrect guesses?  If the guesses always follow the representative sequence
> > (whose existence follows from AC) it's this that allows us to deduce at the
> > end that we've only made finitely many mistakes.
>
> > > That is, you can make all your guesses at random and still be certain
> > > to guess wrong only finitely many times.
>
> > Your proof for this doesn't work...
>
> > Mike.- Hide quoted text -
>
> > - Show quoted text -
>
> At any 1/n point you are guessing according a representative of the
> equivalence class of the eventual sequence, if you just complete the
> sequence of the previous results with random guesses for the finite
> number of the future ones.- Hide quoted text -
>
> - Show quoted text -

This answer of mine is wrong. That does not ensure anything. My point
is made in my Nov 27 response to Tim Little's Nov 26 post. I reproduce
it for courtesy:

"In order to reveal the similarity between this and Benardete's
paradox, put it this way:

First note that what the relevant equivalence class is, is already
determinate at all 1/n points.

Then assume that at any 1/n point I construct it -by guessing at
random the future results- iff I haven't constructed it [in that same
way]* at any 1/m with m>n. Certainly, I possess a representative at
all 1/n points and certainly I construct or choose it at no 1/n point:
so I inherit it, just as Benardete's hearer inherits its deafened
ears.

So, having no need to construct or choose the representative at any 1/
n point I don't need AC.

As I see it, the essential paradox here is that the relevant
equivalence class is already fixed at each 1/n point, so that no toss
contributes to its determination."

*The [] phrase was added.

Best.
From: LauLuna on
On Nov 26, 5:24 pm, WM <mueck...(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de> wrote:

> Of course the game is only possible, if there is an actual infinity
> waiting to be finished. --- And that points to the final period of
> mathematics.

Yes, but that existence is not enough for the game to become possible.

Regards.
From: Tim Little on
On 2009-11-27, LauLuna <laureanoluna(a)yahoo.es> wrote:
> First note that what the relevant equivalence class is, is already
> determinate at all 1/n points.
>
> Then assume that at any 1/n point I construct it -by guessing at
> random the future results- iff I haven't constructed it at any 1/m
> with m>n.

Hence you contradict your original strategy which specified that you
guess at random at every 1/n point. This new strategy is exactly the
AC strategy. It cannot be proven in ZF alone that there exists a set
of representatives covering all equivalence classes, so the strategy
can fail if AC is not assumed.


> As I see it, the essential paradox here is that the relevant
> equivalence class is already fixed at each 1/n point, so that no
> toss contributes to its determination.

Have you seen the "infinite line of prisoners with hats" version
illustrating the same use of AC? In this version, there is an queue
of prisoners, having a back of the queue but extendingly infinitely
forward. Each prisoner can see all the colours of hats worn by those
ahead.

Their task is to guess their own hat colour; if only finitely many
guess incorrectly, they all go free. They get to confer beforehand,
but cannot communicate with each other in any way after the hats are
placed on their heads, and they only get one guess.

In this formulation, there is no question of inheritance or tasks that
cannot be begun.


- Tim
From: William Hughes on
On Nov 26, 4:51 pm, WM <mueck...(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de> wrote:
> On 26 Nov., 19:22, William Hughes <wpihug...(a)hotmail.com> wrote:

> > Only in Wolkenmuekenheim.  Outside of Wolkenmuekenheim
> > you will have an empty set.
>
> Besides your assertion, you have arguments too, don't you?
> In particular you can explain, how the empty set will emerge while
> throughout the whole time the minimum contents of the vase is 1 ball?
>

Since outside of Wolkenmuekenheim there is no reason to
expect the number of balls to be continuous at infinity
outside of Wolkenmuekenheim there is no problem.

Inside of Wolkenmuekenheim we can use "logic" like

All FISONS have a fixed last element.
N does not have a fixed last element.
N is a FISON

and prove anything.

- William Hughes
From: A on
On Nov 26, 3:51 pm, WM <mueck...(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de> wrote:
> On 26 Nov., 19:22, William Hughes <wpihug...(a)hotmail.com> wrote:
>
> > On Nov 26, 12:24 pm, WM <mueck...(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de> wrote:
>
> > > Here is another interesting task: Use balls representing the positive
> > > rationals. The first time fill in one ball. Then fill in always 100
> > > balls and remove 100 balls, leaving inside the ball representing the
> > > smallest of the 101 rationals.
>
> > [at random with any measure that gives a positive probability
> > to each rational]
>
> Simply take the first, seconde, third ... Centuria according to
> Cantor's well-ordering of the positive rationals. Then there is no
> need for considering any probabilities.
>
>
>
> > > If you get practical experience, you
> > > will accomplish every Centuria in half time. So after a short while
> > > you will have found the smallest positive rational.
>
> > Only in Wolkenmuekenheim.  Outside of Wolkenmuekenheim
> > you will have an empty set.
>
> Besides your assertion, you have arguments too, don't you?
> In particular you can explain, how the empty set will emerge while
> throughout the whole time the minimum contents of the vase is 1 ball?
>
> Regards, WM


Let S denote a set with exactly 101 elements. Let Q+ denote the
positive rational numbers. Let inj(S,Q+) denote the set of injective
functions from S to Q+. Let {x_n} denote a sequence of elements of inj
(S,Q+) with the following properties:

1. Let im x_n denote the image of x_n. Then the union of im x_n for
all n is all of Q+.

2. For any n, the intersection of im x_n with im x_(n+1) consists of
exactly one element, which is the minimal element (in the standard
ordering on Q+) in im x_n.

Let X denote the subset of Q+ defined as follows: a positive rational
number x is in X if and only if there exists some positive integer N
such that, for all M > N, x is in the image of x_M.

We are talking about X, right? This is the set of balls which I, and
others, claim is empty, and WM claims is non-empty? Or does WM dispute
one of the definitions above?