From: Dave Seaman on
On Fri, 26 Jan 2007 15:41:28 GMT, Andy Smith wrote:
> Andy Smith <Andy(a)phoenixsystems.co.uk> writes
>>>
>>The point of that argument was intended precisely to show that if a
>>particular arrangement or the reals is countable, then any arrangement
>>is countable, and vice-versa, if a specific ordering of the reals is
>>uncountable, then any arrangement is. I think that is probably not very
>>controversial?
>>
> By "that argument" I meant that advanced in the previous post, not
> Cantor. Sorry for the ambiguity.

I understood that, but it would have been better if you had preserved the
argument you were referring to instead of snipping it.




--
Dave Seaman
U.S. Court of Appeals to review three issues
concerning case of Mumia Abu-Jamal.
<http://www.mumia2000.org/>
From: Franziska Neugebauer on
mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:

>
>
> On 26 Jan., 11:11, Franziska Neugebauer
> <Franziska-Neugeba...(a)neugeb.dnsalias.net> wrote:
>> mueck...(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:
>> > On 25 Jan., 15:57, Franziska Neugebauer
>> > <Franziska-Neugeba...(a)neugeb.dnsalias.net> wrote:
>>
>> >> > If T(oo) as defined by me is T as defined by me, concerning the
>> >> > set of nodes and edges,
>>
>> >>There is no room in equality for "concerning" this or that. Either
>> >>two
>> >> symbols refer to the same entity or they do not.
>>
>> > That is not so obvious.

[indentation corrected:]

>> That *is* obvious.
>
> Indeed?

Indeed. Two sets a and b are equal if

A c (c e a <-> c e b)

Of course only in orthodox set theory possibly not in Augsburg.

F. N.
--
xyz
From: Franziska Neugebauer on
mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:

> Franziska Neugebauer schrieb:
>> mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:
>>
>> > On 25 Jan., 15:34, Franziska Neugebauer
>> > <Franziska-Neugeba...(a)neugeb.dnsalias.net> wrote:
>>
>> context:
>> >> ,----[ <45b5ec2c$0$97243$892e7...(a)authen.yellow.readfreenews.net>
>> >> ]
>> >> | >> Again: Your notations
>> >> | >>
>> >> | >> T(1) U T(2) U ...
>> >> | >>
>> >> | >> and
>> >> | >>
>> >> | >> U {T(i) | i e N }
>> >> | >>
>> >> | >> are undefined.
>> >> | >
>> >> | > You are in error. The union of the trees T(n) and T(n+1) is
>> >> | > defined. n is a natural number. Therefore the union of all
>> >> | > finite trees is defined.
>> >> |
>> >> | You have misunderstood the induction principle. It is not made
>> >> | for "counting over to the infinite".
>> >> `----
>
> Look: Above, there is written "i in N", not "i = N". The latter would
> be missed by induction.

???

>> You have obviously been interested in the "union of all finite trees"
>> which still waits for a definition.
>
> I defined level n and defined the bijection of levels and natural
> numbers. That is enough.

You did not *define* the "union of _all_ finite trees".

>> > It is irrelevant for the consideraton of trees.
>>
>> It is highly relevant to show where your reasoning is malfunctioning.
>
> No. You only try to huddle around, avoiding any concrete discussion.

I have a different understanding of what concrete means. Do you mean the
concrete in your head?

> You cannot make me believe that your intelligence is insufficient to
> understand this discussion.

This may be due to the concrete.

>> > In particular we can prove by induction that the tree, formally
>> > called T(oo),
>>
>> 1. Define T(oo).
>
> Has been done.
>
>> 2. Prove that the "formally called" entity T(oo) is really a tree.
>
> T(oo) is a tree by definition.
>
>>
>> > contains all paths if it contains all levels enumerated by
>> > natural numbers.
>>
>> 1. Define "path".
>
> Look at my tree.

Perhaps I need the Third Eye for that.

>> 2. Define "contains".
>
> Look at Wiki: subset.

"Subsets" is a formal notion which applies to sets not to graphical
sketches on your paper seen by the Third Eye.

>> > We have no use for your set N in the tree (in case it
>> > should differ significantly from the ensmble of all natural
>> > numbers.)
>>
>> Define "ens[e]mble of all natural numbers".
>>
> With pleasure (though it is not simple).
>
> The "ensemble of all natural numbers" is a somehing which cannot be
> named without raising wrong impressions.

I got every nesecessary impression.

F. N.
--
xyz
From: imaginatorium on
Andy Smith wrote:
> Dave Seaman writes
> (snip)

> >> I would say yes,
> >> because there is no scope for any more compact non-infinite
> >> representation of the reals than their infinite binary expansions.
> >
> >Can you prove that?
> >
> And there is the nub of the matter. For me, at this moment, I would say
> that the reals are uncountable because they are infinite, have a
> necessarily infinite binary expansion. That is more than you get from
> Cantor's diagonalisation argument?

What exactly do you mean by "the reals are infinite"? (If just that the
set of reals is infinite - that is, you cannot count all of them and
stop on a number - then so are the natural numbers)

What do you mean by a "necessarily infinite binary expansion"? In what
sense do the algebraic numbers not have a "necessarily infinite binary
expansion"?

(Trouble is that Cantor's diagonalisation argument gives a proof of
something, whereas your somewhat uncollected thoughts are merely
suggestive to someone who thinks they already know the answer.)

Brian Chandler
http://imaginatorium.org

From: MoeBlee on

On Jan 26, 4:25 am, Andy Smith <A...(a)phoenixsystems.co.uk> wrote:

> As I understand it an injection f:A->B means that for every element in A
> , f identifies a unique element of B, but E elements of B not mapped;

I guess by 'E' you mean 'there exist'.

No, we can't conclude that. For a given f, it might be the case that
there are member of B that are not mapped to by f, but just being an
injection from A into B does not entail that there are members of B not
mapped to by f.

> it
> is- one-to-one but not onto.

It is one-to-one and possibly onto B and possibly not onto B.

Here's the definition:

f is an injection from A into B <-> f is a 1-1 function with domain A
and range subset of B.

So the range could be a proper subset of B or it could be B itself.

(By the way, EVERY function is onto the range of the function. So here
it's a question of whether B is the range of f or whether the range of
f is a proper subset of B; and f is still an injection into B either
way.)

> A surjection f:A->B means that f maps every
> element of A onto an element of B such that for every element in B E at
> least one corresponding member of A, but this is not unique (onto but
> not one-to-one)

No, it could also be 1-1, but you got the first part right.

Definition:

f is a surjection from A onto B <-> f is a function with domain A and
range B.

So f might also be 1-1 or it might not be 1-1.

> For the reals to be countable, there has to be an injection from R->N,

Correct.

> but since there is a bijection from N to any infinite subset of N,
It's correct that there is a bijection from N onto any infinite subset
of N, but I don't know why you think this is relevent here.

> for
> the reals to be countable there also has to be a bijection R->N. I
> think?

For R be countable, there has to be a bijection between N and R or a
bijection between a natural number and R. For R to be denumerable,
there has to be a bijection between N and R.

Meanwhile, we have a theorem that, for any X and Y, there is a
bijection between X and Y iff there is both an injection from X into Y
and and injection from Y into X. Now it's trivial to show an injection
from N into R. So if we could show an injection from R into N, then, by
that theorem I mentioned, we'd know that there is a bijection between R
and N.

And that's all correct, but it's not usually the route we take witht
the diagonal argument. Rather, we do this:

The diagonal argument proves, for any f, if f is a function from N into
R, then f is NOT ONTO R. So there is no bijection from N onto R.

In other words, the "list" of reals is a function f from N into R. And
the diagonal argument shows that for any such f, it is NOT ONTO R. So
since a bijection between N and R would have to be a 1-1 function from
N onto R, there can be no such bijection since there is no function of
any kind that is from N onto R.

> If there exists a bijection R->N , there will then be a 1:1 mapping
> between N and R taken in any order (given a bijection between R->N we
> can swap the mappings from N to R as a chain so that we can map R in ANY
> order (i.e. any permutation) that we choose).

I don't know what YOU'RE definition of 'chain' is, but a permutation is
a 1-1 function from a set onto itself.

> So if we can show that there is no one to one mapping between N and R
> taken in some given order, then that would imply that there is no
> bijection R->N ?
>
> I think.

If there is no bijection between X and Y, then no permuation of X nor
any permutation of Y will lead to a bijection between X and Y, is the
best I can answer without further specification of what you're tyring
to say.

Or, maybe you mean a permuation of f itself. In other words, maybe you
are thinking of taking the function f and mapping itself onto itself.
If that's what you have in mind, then, no, that won't work to construct
a bijection between X and Y. Yes, CERTAIN functions may fail to be a
bijection between X and Y while certain other functions are a bijection
between X and Y. But if there does not exist any bijection between X
and Y, then no permuting or anything else will make a bijection between
X and Y.

MoeBee