From: Franziska Neugebauer on
mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:

> I am interested in the fact that every set of natural numbers has a
> finite maximum.

Then you should perhaps not talk to contemporary set theorists who are
accustomed to the fact that there *are* sets of natural numbers which do
not have maxima at all.

F. N.
--
xyz
From: mueckenh on


On 27 Jan., 16:52, Franziska Neugebauer <Franziska-
Neugeba...(a)neugeb.dnsalias.net> wrote:

Please define path:

We need only path-lengths n.
>
>
> > for instance the path p on the outmost left hand side of the tree.In the sequence-of-nodes picture this is the path
>
> p = { (0, 2^i) | i e omega }

Ok, but it is not necessary to consider the whole tree and to count
all its nodes and to sort out those belonging to the path.
>
The length of p_n is a number which has numbers (0 path-lengths) *as
elements*.
In the union of numbers, the numbers are elements. Every natural
number is a set the elements of which are all smaller natural
numbers.
n = {0,1,2,...,n-1}
The lengths of the paths in the union of path-lengths are represented
by natural numbers.

> We call p_n n e omega the finite left-path of length n + 1:

Better say of length n: p_n := { (0, 2^0), ..., (n-1, 2^(n-1)) } ,
but this is not important.
>
> p_n := { (0, 2^0), ..., (n, 2^n) }


>
> Let P_l be the set of all finite left-paths:

The length of p_n is a number which as elements has numbers.
>
> P_l := { p_n | n e omega }
>
> This set only exists if omega exists.

Proof by definition?

P_I includes all p_n which exist. The existence is guaranteded by the
Peano axioms.
We must not assume something which is under examination like omega.

> (If we assumed omega not to exist
> P_l and the set of all finite left-paths would not provably exist).

It is sufficient that the path with length n implies the existence of
the path with length n+1.
>
> Since we assume that omega exists (we do so in contemporary set theory)

which is just under investigation. Therefore we do not do so here.

> P_l exists.

We are interested in the length of the path which is the union of the
lengths of all finite paths.

> According to the axiom of union even the union U P_l
> exists.

Maybe, but that is not at all an interesing question in this context.
The interesting question is alone whether the union of finite lengths
can be an infinite length.

> As one can easily show it is true that
>
> U P_l = p

We are not interesed in p but in the length n of p which length is a
union of some finite lengths.
>
> > Therefore all the path-*lengths* in the union are natural numbers.1. The union of paths is itself is not "many paths" but (at least) is
> single path. *In* the union there is no single paths as member.

In the union of lengths there are all finite lengths. Is this infinite
union of finite lenths a finite length? That is the question.

> The
> union is equal to the path p. The length of path p is (by definition)
> not a natural number.

How can a union of finite numbers yield an infinite number? This is by
definition impossible.

> Its length is card(p) = card(omega) +_card 1
> = card(omega).
>
> 2. P_l contains paths each of which has finite length (depth). Namely
> depth(p_n) = card(p_n) + 1 = n + 1 n e omega.

First you have to answer the question above before your definition
can be accepted.

>
> True. U P_l = p has infinite cardinality.

Maybe or not, but this is uninteresting. The union of pathlengths
contains every single pathlength as a member.
>
> > then at least one of the paths in the union must be infinite.The union does not contain any single path as member (element!).
> P_l does contain only finite paths p_n n e omega as members.

So it cannot include an infinite path?
>
> > Is this so?You proved that silly questions do really exist.
>
> 1. Define "in the union":
> a) there is no member (element) in U P_l = p which is a path

Uninteresting. The *length* of P_I is in question.

> b) there are subsets of U P_l which are paths. Namely
> every p_n n e omega and p itself are subsets of U P_l.
> (p is no a proper subset though).
>
> 2. You probably mean be a member of P_l (the set of all finite
> left-paths). Here indeed every p_n n e omega is element of P_l.
> But p is not an element of P_l, since P_l only contains finite
> paths.

The length of P_I is asked.
>
> Probably you confuse P_l and U P_l.

No, I strictly mean the length of P_I, the union of all finite paths.
I know that you think and define and mean to have proved that U P_I
was infinite.
That is boring.

>
> All in all you presented today next version of your 2003's theme
>
> X is not finite -> there must be an x in X which is infinite
>
> cast into paths. What comes next?

Correct items will not change. The only improvement can concern better
comprehensibility by you.

Regards, WM

From: William Hughes on


On Jan 27, 4:43 pm, mueck...(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:
> On 27 Jan., 17:41, "William Hughes" <wpihug...(a)hotmail.com> wrote:
>
>
>
> > On Jan 27, 8:33 am, mueck...(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:
>
> > > On 25 Jan., 23:33, Virgil <vir...(a)comcast.net> wrote:
> > > > Then you best conclusion is that it holds for all natural numbers but
> > > > not that it holds for N.
> > >Precisely that is what I want and what I do!

> > No proving that something holds for every natural
> > number is not the same as showing that it holds
> > for N.
>
> > Consider
>
> > Every set L_n = {0,1,2,3,....,n} has the property
> > that the maximum of L_n can never refer to more that one natural
> > number.
>
> > The maximum of the set N can refer to more than
> > one natural number.

> I do not want to prove something about a maximum of the set N. I am
> interested in the fact that every set of natural numbers has a finite
> maximum.
>

You claim that if something is true for every set L_n,
then it is true for N.

We know something about the maximum that is true
for every set L_n.

So you do want to prove something about the maximum
of the set N.

- William Hughes

From: Franziska Neugebauer on
mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:

> On 27 Jan., 16:52, Franziska Neugebauer <Franziska-
> Neugeba...(a)neugeb.dnsalias.net> wrote:
[...]
> How can a union of finite numbers yield an infinite number? This is by
> definition impossible.

The following applies:

>> All in all you presented today next version of your 2003's theme
>>
>> X is not finite -> there must be an x in X which is infinite
>>
>> cast into paths. What comes next?
>
> Correct items will not change.

Quantifier dyslexia?

F. N.
--
xyz
From: Andy Smith on
Randy Poe <poespam-trap(a)yahoo.com> writes
>
>
>
(snip)
>That's not an argument. It's a statement about why several of
>your intuitions combine in a certain way to lead you to an
>intuitive conclusion. I don't know what "uncountable" means
>to you, or why "necessarily infinite binary expansion" implies
>whatever that means to you.
>
>I do know that the set of infinite binary strings is uncountable,
>but I know that because it is easily proven.
>
Well, at the high risk of ridicule and a rather lower probability of
assassination by irate set theorists, I think that Cantor's
diagonalisation argument has a terminal flaw.

The flaw is that Cantor's argument, disregarding any qualms about the
infinite sets involved, just demonstrates that one cannot construct an
infinite list of all permutations of binary strings. this is not the
same as showing that you cannot construct an infinite list of all reals,
because, as has been pointed out, reals may have more than one
representation in any base.

Please consider the following, and then abuse me; I hope that this will
cause intense discomfort, but I doubt that it will.

Consider first Cantor's diagonalisation argument applied to the set of
reals in [0,1), i.e. excluding the point 1.00....

Assume that we can form a hypothetically infinite list of the reals. The
countability or otherwise is not a finction of arrangement, so consider
the list set out in the following systematic order, defined by the
mirror inverse of the indices to the hypothetical list:

Index no. Index in binary Corresponding real number
0 0 .0000...
1 1 .1000..
2 10 .0100..
3 11 .1100..
4 100 .0010..

etc.

This arrangement systematically covers all the reals (subject to our
assumption) - it is just the mirror inverse of counting from 0 upwards
in binary.

The maximum number of bits required to describe any index no. i is
ceiling(log(i+1,base 2)). For all i>0, i+1> ceiling(log(i+1,base 2)).
And for i = 0, the real number is 0.000 . So, all terms on the diagonal
are 0 (and, more of this later, the distance in bits between the 0 on
the diagonal and the first non zero bit goes as (n - log(n,base2)) for
bit n.

Following Cantor, we construct an antidiagonal number, different from
the first row, the second row, etc. Because all the diagonal terms are
0, we construct the number .1111....

This string is certainly not in the hypothetically complete list, but it
is a real number and = 1.000... , which was excluded anyway from our
initial list. So we can make no inference that the list is
incomplete/invalid - we have just generated a number.

If we try to rectify that by considering the interval [0,1], on the
systematic numbering scheme above we would insert 1.00.. as the second
entry in our list.:

Index no. Corresponding real number
0 0.0000..
1 1.0000...
2 0.1000..
2 0.0100..
3 0.1100..
4 0.0010..

The antidiagonal for this would be 1.11111... aka 10.000... which is
another valid real which wasn't on our original list.

It is worse than that. If we consider the open interval (0,1), our
systematic ordering is:

Index no. Index in binary Corresponding real number
1 1 .1000..
2 10 .0100..
3 11 .1100..
4 100 .0010..

Our Cantor antidiagonal is then .00111111... aka .010..... which is the
second element of our list.

In general, with this arrangement of the reals, the diagonal must
terminate in in a series of 00000000..., the antidiagonal as a series of
11111111... and the corresponding real either exist already in the list
or outside of it.

With this arrangement, Cantor's diagonalisation argument does not
contradict a hypothesis that one can construct a list of the reals.

that does not mean that it is possible to count the reals, it just
invalidates the argument. Conceivably one might be able to define an
arrangement of reals such that the antidiagonal was unambiguous in
defining a real that should be in the list (but can't be becaue by
construction it is different from those in the list). But if the
argument above is valid, then I think Cantor's diagonalisation is dead
and buried.

That doesn't mean that the reals are countable - far from it. On the
hypothesis that the rals are countable, we ahave a situation where, on
our list, for all entries n in the hypothetical list n e N, the number
of zeroes between the last non zero term and the diagonal bit increases
monotonically as log(n)-loglog(n). So there can never be any non-zero
bits crossing the diagonal. But what about e.g. sqrt(2) ? Any real in
the set with an infinite binary expansion will intersect the diagonal.

You can't construct a numbered list of the reals.

Abuse/explanations/condescension please...
--
Andy Smith