From: Transfer Principle on
On Feb 7, 11:20 am, zuhair <zaljo...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
> > You are being either disingenious, or willfully obtuse.
> same to be said of you also.

This is the week that I plan on returning to work on the
so-called "crank" ellipsis problem. But as I return to
regular posting here at sci.math, I can't help but notice
this current zuhair thread.

Before my extended absence, I often looked to zuhair as
being an ex-"crank," an example of a poster who started
out as a "crank" who attacked standard set theory, but is
now regarded as someone who merely wants to create his own
theories without attacking ZF. But this thread is making
many poster reconsider whether zuhair has really reformed
after all or returning to his old "crank"-ish habits.

Now is as good a time as any to summarize what I believe
now to be three chief differences between the "cranks" and
the standard theorists. Keep in mind that these are mainly
generalizations and may not necessary describe every
individual poster.

I. Standard theorists think of mathematics in terms of the
objects that they want to _exist_ in their own conception
of the mathematical universe. For example, the complete
ordered field is certainly a desirable object (since a
field allows addition, subtraction, multiplication, and
nonzero division to be always defined, order allows one to
compare objects in terms of less than and greater than, and
completeness allows for certain sequences to converge and
establish continuity). Thus, standard theorists work in
theories which prove the existence of such an object, the
complete ordered field.

"Cranks," on the other hand, think of mathematics in terms
of the objects that they _don't_ want to exist. Thus, a
"crank" might declare that they don't want any uncountable
sets to exist. Since the complete ordered field is provably
uncountable, the "crank" would rather work in a theory in
which no complete ordered field can exist than one in which
any uncountable set exists. In other words, avoiding all
uncountable sets is more important to "cranks" than having
a complete ordered field.

II. Standard theorists believe that physics favors their
side of the debate. Physical processes can be modeled by
differential equations, which require the existence of a
complete ordered field to solve. Thus, they believe that
standard analysis is necessary for the sciences, and so
science is impossible in the "crank" theories.

"Cranks," on the other hand, believe that physics favors
their own side of the debate. It's possible that space and
time are quantized, and there may be only finitely many
particles in the physical universe. Thus, "cranks" believe
that all of physics can be modeled using only finite
mathematics, and the standard theorists have theories which
prove the existence of sets such as P(P(P(R))), which to
them have no physical justification.

III. Standard theorists prefer the use of symbolic object
language to natural metalanguage. To standard theorists,
natural languages such as English lack the mathematical
precision of symbolic language, and so all axioms must be
stated using symbolic language only. An axiom written in
metalanguage isn't truly an axiom to standard theorists.

"Cranks," on the other hand, prefer the use of metalanguage
to object language. To "cranks," purely symbolic language
lacks the direct applicability to real-world phenomena that
can be described in metalanguage, and that working with
symbolic language is merely playing around with symbols. An
axiom written in object language isn't truly an axiom to
the "cranks."

To me, both sides have a point. For example, in III, it's
known that human metalanguages aren't precise enough for
computer programming, which is why computer languages had
to be invented. Indeed, computers can now verify simple
proofs written in symbolic language (Metamath). This is a
point in favor of the standard theorists.

But when I write axioms, I sometimes prefer the use of
metalanguage to object language in certain situations. For
to me, it's easier to understand the axiom:

R is an equivalence relation

than it is to understand:

Axyz (xRx & (xRy <-> yRx) & ((xRy & yRz) <-> xRz)).

And some axioms, such as:

R is a wellorder

would be especially cumbersome to write, and even if the
axiom were written out completely, it would take several
minutes to decipher what all the symbols mean, when one can
read "R is a wellorder" and understand what the axiom is
saying in mere seconds. These concepts of "equivalence
relation," "wellorder," etc., are expected to be well known
to most readers of sci.math, and so it's easier for me to
write "R is a wellorder" and have it be understood than
writing the same in pure object language. But on the other
hand, if I am writing about a brand new concept rather than
an established concept, then I'd rather write in object
language in order to introduce the new concept.

I've decided that I would expanded my definition of "crank"
and finally admit that for some individuals, the label
"crank" is actually justified. I like to defend nonstandard
theories, but I'm doing no one, not even the "_cranks_,"
any favors by defending almost any proposed theory. Indeed,
a "crank" may get a "boost" by seeing my defense of his
theory, until he sees me defend a theory even crazier than
his own, at which point the "crank" is thinking, "Oh, the
only person who'll defend my theory is that guy who'll
defend almost any garbage theory." Thus, it will be helpful
to both standard theorists and "cranks" alike for me to be
more selective as to which theories I'll defend.

Formerly, I've stated that I'll defend any theory that isn't
contradicted by ultrafinitism. Now, I'll tighten up and
defend only theories not contradicted by _finitism_. The
problem with ultrafinitism is that whenever a ultrafinitist
tries to claim an upper bound M on the set of admissible
natural numbers, a standard theorist can merely counter that
the choice of upper bound M is arbitrary, even if the
ultrafinitist attempts to give a justification from physics
for the bound M. Therefore, _ultra_finitists such as WM and
Yessenin-Volpin will now be considered cranks (and that's
_without_ the scare quotes, since the label is deserved). On
the other hand, mere finitism only holds that every set is
finite, but there is no upper bound on how large a set is
allowed to be. As for now, finitists who are labeled by
standard theorists as "cranks" will still retain the
scare quotes.

(On the other hand, if Ed Nelson successfully completes his
proof of the inconsistency of PA and ZFC based on the
existence of large numbers, then ultrafinitism would at once
be _justified_, and if Nelson shows that it's the existence
of numbers larger than a certain number M that leads to the
inconsistence, then that M wouldn't be an _arbitrary_ upper
bound, but rather an upper bound that's necessary to avoid
a contradiction, in order to invent a new theory that seeks
to avoid the inconsistency he finds in PA/ZFC.)

We now return to zuhair, and use the above criteria to
determine whether he now deserves the label "crank" or not:

I. Right now, zuhair appears to be denying the existence of
uncountable sets, and is trying to come up with theories
which preclude their existence. This is a point in favor of
the standard theorists that the label "crank" is justified.

II. Now zuhair rarely refers to physics, so this criterion
is irrelevant to the discussion.

III. We see that zuhair regularly uses both object language
and metalanguage to write his axioms. Thus zuhair writes:

> However this bijective correspondence might fail in other set
> theories, and I gave an example of such a theory T that do not have
> an empty set, and that have Quine atoms, and lets say it has two
> primitive constants O and H so now the set of all maps f:Q -> {O,H}
> would be {<Q,O>, <Q,H>} which is bigger than the power set of Q
> which is Q itself, since we have Q={Q} since Q is a Quine atom.

which contains metalanguage, but then he writes a modified
Axiom of Separation:

> Exist y (P(y)) -> For all A exist x for all y ( y e x <-> ( y e A &
> P(y) ) )

which is pure object language.

We notice that zuhair here is describing what I once called
"zuhair's Original Theory (ZOT)," because it is one of the first
theories that he posted here at sci.math. The idea behind ZOT was
that Russell's Paradox prohibits naive comprehension:

ExAy (yex <-> P(y))

So zuhair replaced this with a similar-looking schema:

ExAy (yex <-> (y=x v P(y))

This was supposed to avoid Russell's paradox because if one let
P(y) be the formula "~yey," then we obtain:

ExAy (yex <-> (y=x v ~yey))

Combining this with another axiom, which, among other things,
precludes the existence of the empty set:

Ax (xex)

we derive the theorem:

ExAy (yex <-> y=x)

The set whose existence is guaranteed by this theorem is the
Quine atom Q mentioned in zuhair's post above.

Notice that denying the existence of the _empty_ set may seem
even more "crank"-ish than merely denying the existence of
uncountable sets. But if zuhair can really come up with an
elegant comprehension schema that's as simple as naive
comprehension but without the contradiction, and the cost of
that schema is that the empty set no longer exists, then I
would consider it a small price to pay for the new schema,
and so zuhair wouldn't deserve to be called "crank."

But unfortunately, the set theorist Randall Holmes (the
inventor of Pocket Set Theory) proved that (depending on how
exactly it is written) ZOT is either inconsistent or admits
only models of cardinality 1 (i.e., they prove that every set
is equal to the Quine atom Q, so that Q is the only set). So
zuhair has no longer considered ZOT.

This is why it seems interesting that zuhair has suddenly
returned to a theory which, like ZOT, precludes the existence
of the empty set and proves that the simplest set is Q, the
Quine atom. Then again, this theory isn't equivalent to ZOT
in that his new Separation Schema only prevents the empty set
from existing without requiring every set to contain itself as
an element.

So the final verdict on whether I'll consider calling zuhair a
"crank" to be justified? If by dropping the empty set and
admitting the Quine atom, zuhair comes up with an interesting
theory with some nontrivial sets that are non-Cantorian (i.e.,
fail to be strictly smaller than their own powersets), which
may be finite or possibly infinite, then I'll consider his
theory in more detail, and declare that the "crank" label is
definitely unjustified. If, on the other hand, the only set
that turns out to be non-Cantorian is the Quine atom itself,
then I'll declare the theory to be pointless and lean toward
the standard theorists in dropping the scare quotes when
labelling zuhair.
From: Peter Webb on
I don't think zuhair is a "crank" in the more general Usenet sense. He does
appear to eventually agree he was wrong, which cranks don't - they either
change the topic, make an ad-hominem attack, or do both.

And of course your views on crankdom are very specific to logic.

One thing I disagreed on:

II. Standard theorists believe that physics favors their
side of the debate. Physical processes can be modeled by
differential equations, which require the existence of a
complete ordered field to solve. Thus, they believe that
standard analysis is necessary for the sciences, and so
science is impossible in the "crank" theories.

______________________________________
All physical science can be done using only the countable (but uncomputable)
set of computable Reals. Calculus also works fine over this subset of R.
There is no hard evidence to me that uncountable sets need exist in nature
at all. I grant that it would be somewhat arbitrary for magnetic field
strengths to only take only computable values, but for all we know they may
do so. You might call this UltraCountabilism in comparison to UltraFinitism
!

This tie back to physical processes is also (IMHO) of no value at all to
validating set theory. At the risk of sounding somewhat crankish myself, the
classical analogy between AxC and Euclid's parallel postulate demonstrates
the point. In this Universe, parallel lines do in fact grow closer and quite
possibly intersect 20 billion light years away. That doesn't invalidate
Euclidean geometry, but the parallel postulate is simply not true in the
real world. Its not inconceivable (just very unlikely) that physical
processes could exist which demonstrate that AxC is, or isn't, true in this
Universe. Quantum mechanics gives us a possible starting place; a photon or
particle has to choose in a sense what polarisation/position/momentum etc to
show when an observation is made. Picking one value over another purely on
the basis of probability is a form of Choice.

Indeed, if you accept that you can make precise measurements of anything at
all in nature, and you believe in QM, then in this Universe I can well order
the Reals. I do so as follows. I place an electron inside an energy well
such that its location between 0 and 1 is randomly determined by QM. The
location at which I precisely measure the electron is the lowest (first)
Real. Then I continue doing so for the second and subsequent measurements,
making sure each time I haven't listed that Real already. In this manner, I
can select a random Real from any subset of Reals, which in ZFC requires a
limitted form of choice. The random outcomes in QM provides a mechanism not
directly available inside ZF for choosing elements, and may provide a choice
function in this Universe.

The point of all this being it is very dangerous to try and use the physical
world to validate set theory.





From: Tim Little on
On 2010-02-04, zuhair <zaljohar(a)gmail.com> wrote:
> On the other hand the Diagonal argument seems to require well
> ordering

The *mathematical* content of the diagonal argument is simply this:
for any f:X->A^X, show that there exists g in A^X having the property
that for all x, g(x) != f(x)(x). Therefore no such f is surjective.

No well-ordering is used, in fact no ordering at all.

The argument gets its name from the f(x)(x) terms which lie on the
"diagonal" of a table of the function. The illustrative table that
gives the argument its name is not required for the proof itself,
though, which works for sets that cannot possibly be illustrated.


- Tim
From: Tim Little on
On 2010-02-04, zuhair <zaljohar(a)gmail.com> wrote:
> I was speaking of the diagonal argument that uses infinite binary
> sequences, and not of the other kinds of arguments (although Arturo
> say they the same).

An infinite binary sequence *is defined as* a function from N to
{0,1}, and the set of all such functions is 2^N. The theorem is that
no f:N->2^N is surjective. The diagonal proof is that there exists g
in 2^N such that for all n, g(n) != f(n)(n). The sequence h in 2^N
defined by h(n) = f(n)(n) is called "the diagonal".

Now do you see why they are the same?


>> The argument using the map that Russell's Paradox presented, and which
>> gives the proof for the above almost at once, remains the same...
>
> what Russell's paradox has to do with this?

It is an instance of a very similar type of construction. However,
you are confused enough about the basic diagonal argument that I doubt
it would be fruitful to discuss it any further.


- Tim
From: Nam Nguyen on
Transfer Principle wrote:

>
> I. Standard theorists think of mathematics in terms of the
> objects that they want to _exist_ in their own conception
> of the mathematical universe.
>
> "Cranks," on the other hand, think of mathematics in terms
> of the objects that they _don't_ want to exist.

What about those posters who subscribe to none of those "thinking"?
Are they "crank", or "standard"?