From: Herman Jurjus on
Aatu Koskensilta wrote:
> There are certainly games for which this
> quantifier switch isn't valid (and I'm still bewildered by your
> suggestion this is an instance of failure of the law of excluded
> middle), so any argument or explanation for the evidence of AD must
> depend in an essential way on the games being subsets of the Baire space
> of descriptive set theory.

(The following won't convince Aatu, but i post it anyhow, for other
readers, who perhaps are also puzzled why LEM was brought up.)

Indeed, someone who considers AD to be true seems to be excluding 'too
badly behaved' sets from set theory.

Alternatively, however, he could hold that these complex sets do exist,
but LEM fails for them. I.e. that
"forall x in w^w [ x in A or x not-in A ]"
is not true for them (true for Borel sets, etc., but not for all sets in
general). By dropping LEM for non-Borel sets in this way, things
suddenly start to make much more sense to me. Because you can still have
the 'either player 1 can win, or player 2 can prevent 1 from winning' -
but the defense is not necessarily a winning strategy for player 2 - the
game is no longer one that satisfies the condition that 'at the end of
the game, either player 1 has won or he has not'.

(Anyway - just for what it's worth.)

--
Cheers,
Herman Jurjus
From: Daryl McCullough on
Aatu Koskensilta says...

>A very simple reason to be suspicious of AD is that it amounts to a
>strong form of quantifier switch that is in general not valid.

That's what I was arguing.

>I really couldn't make anything of your comments about the law of excluded
>middle, which isn't involved.

Well, I think I can understand why it *seems* like excluded middle
might be involved.

Let W be a set of sequences of naturals. To say that the first
player can force a win is to say, informally, that
there is a move by the first player such that for any move
of the second player, there is a countermove by the first
player such that, blah, blah. We can introduce a notion of
"infinitely many quantifiers" to express this:

Ex_1 Ax_2 Ex_3 ... [x_1, x_2, ...] in W

I haven't said what this notation means, precisely, but you
should have a fuzzy notion of what it might mean. Using the
same ... notation, we can express "the second player can
force a win" as:

Ax_1 Ex_2 Ax_3 ... [x_1, x_2, ...] not in W

These two statements *appear* to be negations of each other,
if we sloppily assume that the De Morgan's laws apply to
infinitely many quantifiers. So, the law of excluded middle
seems to say that one or the other must be the case.

Of course, this depends on giving a precise semantics to
infinitely many quantifiers, which I haven't done.

To me, to say that something is intuitively true, but not
provable, means that there actually is a sloppy proof, which
possibly glosses over distinctions and subtleties.

There is another point to be made about strategies and
quantifiers. As Butch pointed out, even for a *single*
alternation of quantifiers, the equivalence of

Ax_1 Ex_2 [x_1, x_2] not in W

and

Ef Ax_1 [x_1, f(x_1)] not in W

depends on the axiom of choice, in general. So if AD
involves *denying* the axiom of choice, then we shouldn't
accept alternations of quantifiers as meaning the same
thing as the existence of strategies (represented as
functions). So maybe there is a meaning of the infinite
quantifier case

Ax_1 Ex_2 ... [x_1, x_2, ...] not in W

that is *not* equivalent (without choice) to "there is
a winning strategy (in the sense of function) for the
second player".

--
Daryl McCullough
Ithaca, NY

From: Herman Jurjus on
Aatu Koskensilta wrote:
> Rupert <rupertmccallum(a)yahoo.com> writes:
>
>> When I first read about AD I thought it was an interesting hypothesis,
>> but I never had any feeling that it was intuitively plausible. On the
>> other hand as soon as I encountered AC I was completely convinced that
>> it was true.
>
> Our agreement on these matters is most touching. Let's hug! Before we do
> that, I'll divulge the following piece of information about my personal
> history: when I first encountered determinacy, it immediately struck me
> as obviously false.

Lo and behold: that was also my first reaction, many years ago.
Must be a coincidence.

--
Cheers,
Herman Jurjus
From: Daryl McCullough on
Herman Jurjus says...
>
>Daryl McCullough wrote:
>> Herman Jurjus says...
>>
>>> But: either player 1 has a winning strategy or he hasn't.
>>> Now what does it mean for player 1 to not have a winning strategy?
>>>
>>> I'd say that amounts to 'player 2 has some way to prevent player 1 from
>>> winning'.
>>
>> But that isn't an accurate paraphrase.
>
>I agree that that's a shady part. And of course there's not much more i
>can say. ZFC+AD is inconsistent, so the burden is on me to analyze my
>intuitions further before saying anything more.
>
>> That's the reason I
>> brought up rock/paper/scissors.
>
>Ah. You think that that analogy is good, but i think it isn't.

It's a completely airtight argument that the *lack* of a strategy
for one player does not imply (without additional assumptions) the
existence of a strategy for the other player. What are those
additional assumptions?

>If it were, it should be piece-a-cake to come up with a counterexample
>of AD.

No, that doesn't follow.

It's not an argument that AD is *false*. It shows
that the argument *for* it uses an invalid principle:
"If there is no winning strategy for the first player,
then there must be a winning strategy for the second player".

That's true for some types of games, and false for other
types of games. So it can't be used as a general principle.

--
Daryl McCullough
Ithaca, NY

From: Herman Jurjus on
Daryl McCullough wrote:
> Herman Jurjus says...
>> Daryl McCullough wrote:
>>> Herman Jurjus says...
>>>
>>>> But: either player 1 has a winning strategy or he hasn't.
>>>> Now what does it mean for player 1 to not have a winning strategy?
>>>>
>>>> I'd say that amounts to 'player 2 has some way to prevent player 1 from
>>>> winning'.
>>> But that isn't an accurate paraphrase.
>> I agree that that's a shady part. And of course there's not much more i
>> can say. ZFC+AD is inconsistent, so the burden is on me to analyze my
>> intuitions further before saying anything more.
>>
>>> That's the reason I
>>> brought up rock/paper/scissors.
>> Ah. You think that that analogy is good, but i think it isn't.
>
> It's a completely airtight argument that the *lack* of a strategy
> for one player does not imply (without additional assumptions) the
> existence of a strategy for the other player. What are those
> additional assumptions?

No hidden moves (where this includes 'adjourned' moves and simultaneous
moves), no chance-moves.

--
Cheers,
Herman Jurjus