From: Chris Menzel on
On Thu, 1 Jul 2010 08:41:44 -0700 (PDT), Charlie-Boo
<shymathguy(a)gmail.com> said:
> On Jul 1, 2:04 am, Aatu Koskensilta <aatu.koskensi...(a)uta.fi> wrote:
>> Charlie-Boo <shymath...(a)gmail.com> writes:
>> > To see it means to have actually created it, and its actual creation
>> > would answer the very interesting question of whether ZFC can prove
>> > that PA is consistent even though PA can't.
>>
>> We already know the answer. The axioms used in the proof are a
>> restricted form of comprehension, infinity, union and pairing.
>
> Why do we need each of these? Of course infinity = PA = arithmetic.
> But why are the others needed?

These are the questions you could answer for yourself with just a bit of
study. The tragic thing is, these topics are so marvelously interesting
and yet you insist on dwelling in ignorance. (Infinity = PA? So sad...)

From: Chris Menzel on
On Wed, 30 Jun 2010 21:23:23 -0700 (PDT), Charlie-Boo
<shymathguy(a)gmail.com> said:
> On Jun 29, 9:51 pm, herbzet <herb...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
>> "Jesse F. Hughes" wrote:
>> > Of course, I'm really here for lower entertainment.  I want posts about
>> > the Hammer, about how surrogate factoring moves the stock market, about
>> > the most influential mathematicians on the planet.  But still I pretend
>> > to care about arguments, if only for appearance's sake.
>>
>> Well, I didn't come here for the low comedy -- that's simply not an idea
>> that had occurred to me.  But, it being made explicitly an option -- I
>> suppose it's a valid choice, even one of some value.
>>
>> If I have any reservation, it would just be that I don't think that
>> encouraging crankery for its entertainment value
>
> crank: "an unbalanced person who is overzealous in the advocacy of a
> private cause"

You're talking about you and CBL, right?

From: Frederick Williams on
Charlie-Boo wrote:
>
> On Jul 1, 3:50 pm, Frederick Williams <frederick.willia...(a)tesco.net>
> wrote:
> > Charlie-Boo wrote:
> > > No, PA and ZFC both have Peano's Axioms.
> >
> > What formulations of first order PA and ZFC have _any_ of their
> > non-logical axioms in common? None. Why? Well, for starters, all of
> > the proper axioms of ZFC have the predicate symbol $\in$ in them, none
> > of PA's axioms do because $\in$ is not even in the language of PA
> >
> > > The only difference is the
> > > universal set, which is N in PA
> >
> > There are no sets, universal or otherwise, in first order PA.
>
> What does (existsX)P(X) mean?

It means that there's a natural number which has property P.

--
I can't go on, I'll go on.
From: MoeBlee on
On Jul 1, 5:52 pm, herbzet <herb...(a)gmail.com> wrote:
> MoeBlee wrote:
>
> > CORRECTION below:
>
> > On Jul 1, 5:10 pm, MoeBlee <jazzm...(a)hotmail.com> wrote:
>
> > > However, even though the definition I gave is okay, and provides these
> > > theorems,
>
> > > a theory T is inconsistent <-> T proves a contradiction
>
> > > a set of axioms X for a theory T is inconsistent <-> X proves a
> > > contradiction
>
> > Oops, delete that.
>
> Not sure if "that" is the previous sentence, or the previous 2 sentences.

Good point. Just the previous sentence.

> > > a theory T that is axiomatized by X is inconsistent <-> X proves a
> > > contradiction,
>
> > > I realize that in my own notes I actually do use a different
> > > definition, which, again, is equivalent for THEORIES but different for
> > > arbitrary sets of formulas:
>
> Missing the nuance here, unless you are distinguishing between
> a set Gamma of formulas *implying* both P and ~P, and a set Gamma
> of formulas *containing* both P and ~P.

Lets use 'derives' instead of 'implies' ('entails') so that we're
clearly purely syntactical.

But, yes, my first definition was not as good. Better to say that a
set of formulas G is inconsistent iff we can derive a contradiction
from G.


> > > a set of formulas G is consistent <-> there is no formula P such that
> > > P and ~P are provable from G
>
> OK, so far so good.
>
> > > a set of formulas G is inconsistent <-> G is not consistent
>
> Can't object to that.
>
> > and I think that is an easier and nicer definition to work with as it
> > gives all at once:
>
> > a set of formulas G is inconsistent <-> G proves a contradiction
>
> > a set of formulas G is inconsistent <-> G proves every formula (in the
> > language)
>
> No doubt missing some of the issues here, but:
>
> For classical logic the following sets are extensionally equivalent:
>
> 1) a set of formulas G that proves both P and ~P for some formula P.
> 2) a set of formulas G that proves a contradiction, i.e., some formula (P & ~P).
> 3) a set of formulas G that proves every formula (in the language).

Exactly. You're agreeing with me.

> For non-classical logics, these may diverge.

Of course.
>
> What (3) describes is called a trivial theory.  We don't necessarily
> care so much about inconsistency -- a paraconsistent logic will tolerate
> some inconsistency of type (1) or (2) in a theory T without T's necessarily
> becoming trivial.
>
> We don't worry so much about inconsistency per se -- we worry about
> triviality instead.

From a paraconsistent viewpoint that's true.

So whether we adopt:

consistent <-> derives a contradiction
or
consistent <-> there's a formula not derivable

would determine how the paraconsistent advocate would couch his views
as to consistency, as he would not mind a theory with contradictions
as long as the "explosive property" were absent so that contradictions
don't derive everything.

I think we are in accord, as far as I can tell.

MoeBlee

From: MoeBlee on
On Jul 2, 2:31 am, Chris Menzel <cmen...(a)remove-this.tamu.edu> wrote:

> Peter Smith's wonderfully lucid book _An Introduction to Gödel's
> Theorems_ highly recommended for this.

But make sure to get a newer printing, since he made a number of
important changes.

MoeBlee