From: Martin Shobe on
On Mon, 25 Jul 2005 15:52:08 -0400, Tony Orlow (aeo6)
<aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:

>Martin Shobe said:
>> On Wed, 20 Jul 2005 10:57:58 -0400, Tony Orlow (aeo6)
>> <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:
>>
>> >Barb Knox said:
>> >> In article <MPG.1d4726e11766660c989f2f(a)newsstand.cit.cornell.edu>,
>> >> Tony Orlow (aeo6) <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:
>> >> [snip]
>> >>
>> >> >Infinite whole numbers are required for an infinite set of whole numbers.
>> >>
>> >> Good grief -- shake the anti-Cantorian tree a little and out drops a
>> >> Phillite. Here's a clue: ALL whole numbers are finite. Here's a
>> >> (2nd-order) proof outline, using mathematical induction (which I
>> >> assume/hope you accept):
>> >> 0 is finite.
>> >> If k is finite then k+1 is finite.
>> >> Therefore all natural numbers are finite.
>> >>
>> >>
>> >That's the standard inductive proof that is always used, and in fact, the ONLY
>> >proof I have ever seen of this "fact". Is there any other? I have three proofs
>> >that contradict this one. Do you have any others that support it?
>> >
>> >Inductive proof proves properties true for the entire set of naturals, right?
>>
>> Yep.
>>
>> >That entire set is infinite right?
>>
>> Yep.
>>
>> >Therfore, the number of times you are adding
>> >1 and saying, "yep, still finite", is infinite, right?
>>
>> Yep. But be careful here, at *every* stage of this process, we have
>> still only done it a finite number of times.
>Uhhh.... Look at what you just agreed to. The number of times you are adding 1
>is infinite. But, now you say it is always a finite number of times? make up
>your mind.

It's quote made up. I have chosen to follow the route you so
cavalierly ignored.

>> > So, you have some way of
>> >adding an infinite number of 1's and getting a finite result?
>>
>> Nope. You weren't careful.
>You contradicted yourself. Do you apply successor and increment the value a
>finite number of times, or an infinite number of times? Be careful.

There is no end to how much I can apply successor. However, I can
only apply it a finite number of times. No contradiction here.

>> > You might want to
>> >discuss this with your colleagues specializing in infinite series. There is a
>> >very simple rules that says no infinite series can converge to a finite value
>> >unless the terms of the series have a limit of zero as n approaches infinity.
>> >Does this constant term, 1, have a limit of zero?
>>
>> Nope.
>>
>> > No it doesn't, and the
>> >infinite series of constant 1's cannot converge, but diverges to infinity.
>>
>> Yep.
>>
>> > Can
>> >you actually deny this? If so, then Poincare was right.
>>
>> BTW, there is a caveat on convergence. You have to assume the
>> standard topology. In other topologies, that sequence can converge.
>You mean with a ring?

No. One example would be to use the trivial topology. In this
topology, every sequence converges to every value.

Martin

From: Virgil on
In article <MPG.1d4f0a8eab9b915f989f7c(a)newsstand.cit.cornell.edu>,
Tony Orlow (aeo6) <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:


> Actually, whether you are talking about reals in [0,1) or n in N, or
> ANY infinite set of elements represented as strings of symbols, in
> order to have an infinite set, you either need an infinite set of
> symbols, or infinitely long strings. To the right of the point, these
> infinitely long digital strings represent finite values, whereas to
> the left, they represent infinite values (mostly). This is a fact of
> any symbolic systems.
> >
> > I'm sure I'm not the only one to suggest the following, but here
> > goes:
> >
> > 1. Note that the successor function is a 1:1 function from the set
> > of natural numbers to a proper subset. This establishes N as an
> > infinite set, since it is in 1:1 correspondence with a proper
> > subset.
> >
> > 2. Note that the induction axiom (one of the Peano axioms) states:
> >
> > If A is a subset of N that is closed under the successor
> > function, and which contains 0, then A = N.
> >
> > The set of all finite natural numbers satisfies the requirements of
> > the induction axiom. Therefore, the set of finite natural numbers
> > is equal to the set of all natural numbers. In other words, every
> > natural number is finite.
> Take a look at the rewrite of Peano's axioms I posted earlier today.
> >
> > 3. Note that the set of finite natural numbers is (without the
> > induction axiom) already an infinite set by virtue of (1) above:
> > the successor of every finite natural number is another finite
> > natural number, and the set of all successor numbers is a proper
> > subset.
> >
> > Whatever set you take to be the set of natural numbers, if it
> > contains infinite natural numbers, is not the same set that
> > mathematicians are referring to when they use the term "natural
> > numbers".
> Okay. Let's just call them integers.
> >
> > Perhaps you mean to be claiming that there is no model of Peano
> > arithmetic?
> I am claiming that after infinite succession, we have changed values
> by an infinite amount.
> >
> > I'll also note that your "infinite series" argument is not germane.
> > The issue is not whether one *can* formulate infinite series, but
> > whether one *must* formulate these. Arithmetic by itself does not
> > mandate such, nor does algebra. In fact, you nod to that point by
> > raising the notion of convergence, a notion that is decidedly
> > non-algebraic, but instead topological, in nature. The very act of
> > defining convergence and of assigning numerical values to the
> > formal sums that can be written involves an expansion of the notion
> > of summation; if it were not so, then there would be no choice in
> > the matter of assigning the value of sums. Instead, there is a
> > great deal of choice in the matter, viz. p-adic numbers, being
> > completions of the rationals wrt norms other than the usual one. In
> > addition, note that the phenomenon of conditional convergence
> > carries with it the ability to assign the value of a sum to any
> > real value whatsoever by merely rearranging terms.

> That may all be true, but none of it makes it possible to increment a
> value an infinite number of times and get a finite value.


TO requires that we at some point must be able to increment a finite
value once and get an infinite value.


> You are
> adding 1 an infinite number of times to produce the set.

Definition: a natural is finite if the initial segment of naturals of
which it is the largest is a finite set (has no injection into a proper
subset).

(1) The first natural is finite.
(2) if the natural n is finite then the natural n+1 is finite.
By the inductive axiom, it follows that ALL naturals are finite.

If TO's version of natural numbers do not work this way then they are
not the same as Peano's.
From: Virgil on
In article <MPG.1d4f0cf3bdd3d39a989f7e(a)newsstand.cit.cornell.edu>,
Tony Orlow (aeo6) <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:

> Martin Shobe said:
> > On Wed, 20 Jul 2005 10:57:58 -0400, Tony Orlow (aeo6)
> > <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:
> >
> > >Barb Knox said:
> > >> In article
> > >> <MPG.1d4726e11766660c989f2f(a)newsstand.cit.cornell.edu>,
> > >> Tony Orlow (aeo6) <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:
> > >> [snip]
> > >>
> > >> >Infinite whole numbers are required for an infinite set of
> > >> >whole numbers.
> > >>
> > >> Good grief -- shake the anti-Cantorian tree a little and out
> > >> drops a Phillite. Here's a clue: ALL whole numbers are finite.
> > >> Here's a (2nd-order) proof outline, using mathematical induction
> > >> (which I assume/hope you accept):
> > >> 0 is finite. If k is finite then k+1 is finite. Therefore
> > >> all natural numbers are finite.
> > >>
> > >>
> > >That's the standard inductive proof that is always used, and in
> > >fact, the ONLY proof I have ever seen of this "fact". Is there any
> > >other? I have three proofs that contradict this one. Do you have
> > >any others that support it?
> > >
> > >Inductive proof proves properties true for the entire set of
> > >naturals, right?
> >
> > Yep.
> >
> > >That entire set is infinite right?
> >
> > Yep.
> >
> > >Therfore, the number of times you are adding 1 and saying, "yep,
> > >still finite", is infinite, right?
> >
> > Yep. But be careful here, at *every* stage of this process, we
> > have still only done it a finite number of times.
> Uhhh.... Look at what you just agreed to. The number of times you are
> adding 1 is infinite. But, now you say it is always a finite number
> of times? make up your mind.
> >
> > > So, you have some way of
> > >adding an infinite number of 1's and getting a finite result?
> >
> > Nope. You weren't careful.
> You contradicted yourself. Do you apply successor and increment the
> value a finite number of times, or an infinite number of times? Be
> careful.

When, and only when, TO can point to a particular incrementation as the
one which goes from finite to infinite, will he have any case.
> >
> > > You might want to
> > >discuss this with your colleagues specializing in infinite series.
> > >There is a very simple rules that says no infinite series can
> > >converge to a finite value unless the terms of the series have a
> > >limit of zero as n approaches infinity. Does this constant term,
> > >1, have a limit of zero?
> >
> > Nope.
> >
> > > No it doesn't, and the
> > >infinite series of constant 1's cannot converge, but diverges to
> > >infinity.
> >
> > Yep.
> >
> > > Can
> > >you actually deny this? If so, then Poincare was right.
> >
> > BTW, there is a caveat on convergence. You have to assume the
> > standard topology. In other topologies, that sequence can
> > converge.

> You mean with a ring?

If TO does not know what a topology is, he shold not b e talking about
converence and divergence. His ignorance here, as elsewhere in
mathematics, makes him act the fool.

> That's really not what we're talking about,

That's not what toplogy is about, ignoramus.


>
> So, please make up your mind. Do we increment to get a successor an
> infinite number of times, or only a finite number of times, to get N?

Only a finite number of times for any n in N, but without end, but also
never reaching the "end" that is not there.
From: Virgil on
In article <MPG.1d4f0d1369ffd55b989f7f(a)newsstand.cit.cornell.edu>,
Tony Orlow (aeo6) <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:

> Virgil said:
> > In article <MPG.1d4858812235c0b0989f4c(a)newsstand.cit.cornell.edu>,
> > Tony Orlow (aeo6) <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:
> >
> > > David Kastrup said:
> >
> > > > What is supposed to be a "constant equality"?
> >
> >
> > > An equality that holds true for n=1, and for n=n+1 given true for n.
> >
> > In mathematics, n=n+1 is always false.
> >
> excuse the typo. again

Actually it is more likely TO's assumption that mathematics must act
like a special version of C.
From: stephen on
In sci.math malbrain(a)yahoo.com wrote:
> Barb Knox wrote:
>> In article <MPG.1d4ecd45545679a8989f6b(a)newsstand.cit.cornell.edu>,
>> Tony Orlow (aeo6) <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:
>> [snip]
>>
>> >keep in mind that
>> >inductive proof IS an infinite loop, so that incrementing in the loop creates
>> >infinite values, and the quality of finiteness is not maintained over those
>> >infinite iterations of the loop.
>>
>> Using your computational view, consider the following infinite loop
>> (using some unbounded-precision arithmetic system similar to
>> java.math.BigInteger):
>>
>> for (i = 0; ; i++) {
>> println(i);
>> }
>>
>> Now, although this is an INFINITE loop, every value printed will be
>> FINITE. Right?

> Not so fast. The behaviour of incrementing i after it reaches INT_MAX
> is undefined.

There is no INT_MAX for an unbounded-precision arithmetic system.

Stephen