From: Tony Orlow on
Daryl McCullough said:
> Tony Orlow <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> said:
>
> >> > but the diagonal proof suffers from the fatal flaw of assuming that
> >> > the diaginal traversal actually covers all the numbers in the list.
> >> > Any complete list of digital numbers of a given length, even a given
> >> > infinite length, is exponentially longer in members than wide in terms
> >> > of the digits in each member. Therefore, the diagonal traversal only
> >> > shows that the anti- diagonal does not exist in the first aleph_0
> >> > terms.
>
> Yes, that's exactly what the diagonal argument proves. There is
> no list of length aleph_0 that contains all real numbers.
>
> --
> Daryl McCullough
> Ithaca, NY
>
>
Okay, that I can agree with, at least in digital terms, which is what the proof
relies on. Try it with Roman numerals!

What it really shows is that digital systems with a given number of digits have
more strings than digits. it is not necessary to have aleph_0 digits, if you
allow for smaller infinities. You only need SOME infinite number of digits. For
N naturals, you only need log(N) digits to produce a list N long.
--
Smiles,

Tony
From: Tony Orlow on
David Kastrup said:
> Tony Orlow (aeo6) <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> writes:
>
> > Barb Knox said:
> >> In article <MPG.1d4726e11766660c989f2f(a)newsstand.cit.cornell.edu>,
> >> Tony Orlow (aeo6) <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:
> >> [snip]
> >>
> >> >Infinite whole numbers are required for an infinite set of whole numbers.
> >>
> >> Good grief -- shake the anti-Cantorian tree a little and out drops a
> >> Phillite. Here's a clue: ALL whole numbers are finite. Here's a
> >> (2nd-order) proof outline, using mathematical induction (which I
> >> assume/hope you accept):
> >> 0 is finite.
> >> If k is finite then k+1 is finite.
> >> Therefore all natural numbers are finite.
> >>
> >>
> > That's the standard inductive proof that is always used, and in
> > fact, the ONLY proof I have ever seen of this "fact". Is there any
> > other? I have three proofs that contradict this one. Do you have any
> > others that support it?
> >
> > Inductive proof proves properties true for the entire set of
> > naturals, right?
>
> For each of its members.
>
> > That entire set is infinite right? Therfore, the number of times you
> > are adding 1 and saying, "yep, still finite", is infinite, right?
>
> No. He is not adding 1 more than a single time, just to check that
> for n finite (which means that the set 0..n obeys the pigeon-hole
> principle) n+1 is still finite (the case of one additional pigeon-hole
> can be reduced to the case n if you check for the hole in position
> n+1 and in 0..n both before and after permutation).
How do you know 6598367 is finite? Because you got it by adding 1 to 6598366,
the 6598366th number. So how to you get the aleph_0th number? What IS that
number? it's aleph_0.
>
> > So, you have some way of adding an infinite number of 1's and
> > getting a finite result?
>
> No, he is just checking that the conditions for the fifth Peano axiom
> hold. The whole point of the axioms is not to have to check an
> infinite number of steps in order to get a statement about the members
> of a particular infinite set, the naturals.
And yet, one cannot apply an increment an infinite number of time without
adding infinity.
>
> > You might want to discuss this with your colleagues specializing in
> > infinite series. There is a very simple rules that says no infinite
> > series can converge to a finite value unless the terms of the series
> > have a limit of zero as n approaches infinity. Does this constant
> > term, 1, have a limit of zero? No it doesn't, and the infinite
> > series of constant 1's cannot converge, but diverges to
> > infinity. Can you actually deny this? If so, then Poincare was
> > right.
>
> Nobody is bothered about adding numbers. The Peano axioms do not even
> define addition.
Just succession. Addition requires the added notion of measure, but that is
inherent inn the natural numbers. Each one, as a real number, represents its
distance from the origin, 0.
>
>

--
Smiles,

Tony
From: stephen on
In sci.math malbrain(a)yahoo.com wrote:


> Daryl McCullough wrote:
>> Tony Orlow writes:
>> >
>> >Dik T. Winter said:
>>
>> >> Back on your horse again. Tell me about the binary numbers (extended to the
>> >> left with 0's) where the leftmost 1 is in a finite position. Are all those
>> >> numbers finite? Are there only finitely many of them?
>> >
>> >yes and yes
>>
>> What definition of "finite" are you using?

> Main Entry: finite
> Pronunciation: 'fI-"nIt
> Function: adjective
> Etymology: Middle English finit, from Latin finitus, past participle of
> finire
> 1 a : having definite or definable limits <finite number of
> possibilities> b : having a limited nature or existence <finite beings>

> This definition from webster should suffice.

Definitions from webster rarely suffice for mathematical
arguments.

> Binary numbers with ones
> in finite positions have a limited number of possibilities.

> karl m

What is that limit? How is it defined? Do you seriously
believe that there are only a finite number of finite positions?

A binary number with one's in finite positions can have an arbitray
number of one's. There is no limit on the possibilities.
The set of f finite binary strings is infinite.

Stephen
From: Virgil on
In article <MPG.1d48308522352190989f3d(a)newsstand.cit.cornell.edu>,
Tony Orlow (aeo6) <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:

> Barb Knox said:
> > In article <MPG.1d4726e11766660c989f2f(a)newsstand.cit.cornell.edu>,
> > Tony Orlow (aeo6) <aeo6(a)cornell.edu> wrote:
> > [snip]
> >
> > >Infinite whole numbers are required for an infinite set of whole numbers.
> >
> > Good grief -- shake the anti-Cantorian tree a little and out drops a
> > Phillite. Here's a clue: ALL whole numbers are finite. Here's a
> > (2nd-order) proof outline, using mathematical induction (which I
> > assume/hope you accept):
> > 0 is finite.
> > If k is finite then k+1 is finite.
> > Therefore all natural numbers are finite.
> >
> >
> That's the standard inductive proof that is always used, and in fact, the
> ONLY
> proof I have ever seen of this "fact". Is there any other? I have three
> proofs
> that contradict this one. Do you have any others that support it?

Unless TO has a definition of finiteness of naturals that makes the
above proof invalid, one valid proof is enough.

We have yet to see any of TO's alleged counter-proofs that are not
fatally flawed.
>
> Inductive proof proves properties true for the entire set of naturals, right?

Wrong! It proves things only for the MEMBERS of that set, not the set
itself!

Definitions (Cantor):
(1) a set is finite if and only if there do not exist any
injective mappings from the set to any proper subset
(2) a set is infinite if and only if there exists any
injection from the set to any proper subset.
Clearly then, a set is finite if and only if it is not infinite.
Definitions (Auxiliary):
(3) a natural number, n, is finite if and only if the set
of naturals up to it, {m in N: m <= n}, is finite
(4) a natural number, n, is infinite if and only if the set
of naturals up to it, {m in N: m <= n}, is infinite

If these definitions are valid, then it is easy to prove buy induction
that there are no such things as infinite naturals:

(a) The first natural is finite, since there is clearly no
injection from a one member set the empty set.

(b) If any n in N is finite then n+1 is also finite.
This is also while quite clear, though a comprehensive proof
would involvev a lot of details.

By the inductinve axiom, goven (a) and (b), EVERY MEMBER of N is finite,
but that does not say that N is finite.
From: malbrain on
step...(a)nomail.com wrote:
> In sci.math malbrain(a)yahoo.com wrote:
>
>
> > Daryl McCullough wrote:
> >> Tony Orlow writes:
> >> >
> >> >Dik T. Winter said:
> >>
> >> >> Back on your horse again. Tell me about the binary numbers (extended to the
> >> >> left with 0's) where the leftmost 1 is in a finite position. Are all those
> >> >> numbers finite? Are there only finitely many of them?
> >> >
> >> >yes and yes
> >>
> >> What definition of "finite" are you using?
>
> > Main Entry: finite
> > Pronunciation: 'fI-"nIt
> > Function: adjective
> > Etymology: Middle English finit, from Latin finitus, past participle of
> > finire
> > 1 a : having definite or definable limits <finite number of
> > possibilities> b : having a limited nature or existence <finite beings>
>
> > This definition from webster should suffice.
>
> Definitions from webster rarely suffice for mathematical
> arguments.

They are illustrative of how the set of contradictions is resolved by
the majority.

>
> > Binary numbers with ones
> > in finite positions have a limited number of possibilities.
>
> > karl m
>
> What is that limit? How is it defined? Do you seriously
> believe that there are only a finite number of finite positions?
>
> A binary number with one's in finite positions can have an arbitray
> number of one's. There is no limit on the possibilities.
> The set of f finite binary strings is infinite.

Right. We're discussing the number of permutations of each of these
strings taken individually.

karl m

First  |  Prev  |  Next  |  Last
Pages: 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53
Prev: Derivations
Next: Simple yet Profound Metatheorem