Prev: Help with a question - throey of groups using functions
Next: Theory of groups with functions - Help on a question
From: herbzet on 3 Jun 2010 00:24 > Arturo Magidin wrote: > > This is the well-known condition on groups that says that a semigroup > > (a nonempty set with a binary associative operation) is a group if and > > only if for every a and b, the equations > > > > a = bx and a = yb This is nice and neat also. Can you smell the sawdust burning? I'm thinkin'. -- hz
From: George Greene on 3 Jun 2010 00:28 On Jun 2, 10:23 pm, herbzet <herb...(a)gmail.com> wrote: > I think that what's going on is that the variables 'x','y','z' > (from the end of the alphabet) are being instantiated to > constants 'a','b','c' (from the beginning of the alphabet). In order to use the universal-generalization-inference rule at all, you have to come up with a "new" symbol. It does not even matter whether you call it a constant or a variable. Usually it is thought of as an arbitrary constant. > Quantifying over constants is not quite kosher, I think. Maybe not, but if you are going to prove a universally quantified statement, you will probably start with a constant and replace it by a variable as you invoke the rule.
From: Arturo Magidin on 3 Jun 2010 00:30 On Jun 2, 10:59 pm, herbzet <herb...(a)gmail.com> wrote: > herbzet wrote: > > Arturo Magidin wrote: > > > herbzet wrote: > > > > I think that what we want for a third axiom is > > > > > (A3') Axyz [(x.y = x.z) -> (y = z)]. > > > > This may suffice (I haven't checked), but the original A3 is perfectly > > > fine too. > > (A3') reflects that I'm thinking of a group as a Latin square: > > a Latin square is an n × n table filled with n different symbols > in such a way that each symbol occurs exactly once in each row and > exactly once in each column (Wikipedia). > > except I'm allowing the square to have an infinite number of rows > and columns. > > So I'm conceptualizing a group as a (possibly infinite) Latin square > (the group operation matrix) that obeys the associative law. > > I don't know if that's right, but it seems nice and neat. By itself, of course it does not suffice (while the Cayley table of every (finite) group is a (finite) latin square, not every (finite) latin square is the Cayley table of a (finite) group). My only caveat was wether together with left-solutions it would suffice. (Note that if you replaced your (A3') with the similar (A3'') Axyz [yx=zx -> y=z] then my semigroup example would satisfy (A1), (A2), and (A3''), and not be a group. But we can think of this A3'' as being a similarly flavored "latin square" axiom; in conjunction with A2 it says that the solution in A2 is unique, so that every symbol will occur in each column/row [depending how you interpret the first factor] *exactly* once). But my example does not satisfy A1, A2, and A3'. So the question is whether associativity, left cancellation, and solutions on the left imply a group structure. And I've been wavering, but haven't been able to come up with a counterexample (and it's getting late). I'll think about it a bit more. -- Arturo Magidin
From: herbzet on 3 Jun 2010 03:53 Arturo Magidin wrote: > herbzet wrote: > > herbzet wrote: > > > Arturo Magidin wrote: > > > > herbzet wrote: > > > > > I think that what we want for a third axiom is > > > > > > > (A3') Axyz [(x.y = x.z) -> (y = z)]. > > > > > > This may suffice (I haven't checked), but the original A3 is perfectly > > > > fine too. > > > > (A3') reflects that I'm thinking of a group as a Latin square: > > > > a Latin square is an n � n table filled with n different symbols > > in such a way that each symbol occurs exactly once in each row and > > exactly once in each column (Wikipedia). > > > > except I'm allowing the square to have an infinite number of rows > > and columns. > > > > So I'm conceptualizing a group as a (possibly infinite) Latin square > > (the group operation matrix) that obeys the associative law. > > > > I don't know if that's right, but it seems nice and neat. > > By itself, of course it does not suffice (while the Cayley table of > every (finite) group is a (finite) latin square, not every (finite) > latin square is the Cayley table of a (finite) group). Right -- the associative law must hold too. With that constraint, I think my description in English is correct, even for infinite tables -- but I'm not sure. > My only caveat > was wether together with left-solutions it would suffice. Oh, yeah -- I haven't been thinking about left/right issues. Sloppiness on my part. > (Note that > if you replaced your (A3') with the similar > > (A3'') Axyz [yx=zx -> y=z] > > then my semigroup example would satisfy (A1), (A2), and (A3''), and > not be a group. But we can think of this A3'' as being a similarly > flavored "latin square" axiom; in conjunction with A2 it says that the > solution in A2 is unique, so that every symbol will occur in each > column/row [depending how you interpret the first factor] *exactly* > once). > But my example does not satisfy A1, A2, and A3'. So the question is > whether associativity, left cancellation, and solutions on the left > imply a group structure. And I've been wavering, but haven't been able > to come up with a counterexample (and it's getting late). I'll think > about it a bit more. Me too. -- hz
From: Frederick Williams on 3 Jun 2010 11:55 Arturo Magidin wrote: > > On Jun 2, 7:58 am, Frederick Williams <frederick.willia...(a)tesco.net> > wrote: > > Mitchell Hockley wrote: > > > > > (Hint: Use Ez(c = z.a)) > > > > Eh? What if a = 0 and c =/= 0? > > I think you are confused; when we use "a=0" in a group, the operation > is usually taken to be addition, not multiplication. Yes, sorry. I'm an idiot. -- I can't go on, I'll go on.
First
|
Prev
|
Next
|
Last
Pages: 1 2 3 4 5 Prev: Help with a question - throey of groups using functions Next: Theory of groups with functions - Help on a question |