Prev: Help with a question - throey of groups using functions
Next: Theory of groups with functions - Help on a question
From: Robert E. Beaudoin on 10 Jun 2010 01:18 On 06/09/10 12:21, Arturo Magidin wrote: > On Jun 8, 11:45 pm, "Robert E. Beaudoin" <rbeaud...(a)acm.org> wrote: >> On 06/08/10 16:17, Arturo Magidin wrote: >> >> >> >>> On Jun 2, 11:30 pm, Arturo Magidin <magi...(a)member.ams.org> wrote: >> >>> Not a full answer yet. >> >>> So, to recap: suppose you have a [nonempty] set S and a binary >>> operation (which we denote by concatenation) on S such that >> >>> (i) the operation is associative; >>> (ii) for every x and y in S, there exists z such that x = zy; >>> (iii) For every r,s,t in S, if rs = rt, then s=t. >> >>> Will S be a group? >> >>> I'm pretty sure the answer is "no" in general, but I asked a >>> colleague. He did point out that under some mild conditions, the >>> answer is "yes": S will be a group if any of the following hold: >> >>> (a) S contains an idempotent; >>> (b) every cyclic subsemigroup of S is finite; >>> (c) there is at least one cyclic subsemigroup of S that is finite; >>> (d) S is finite. >> >>> To see this, note that (d)->(c)->(b)->(a). Under condition (a), let e >>> be an idempotent. Then for all x in S, eex = ex, so by left >>> cancellation we have that ex=x for all x. Then from (ii) we get that >>> for every x there exists z such that zx=e, and we have both left >>> identity and left inverses, hence a group. >> >>> -- >>> Arturo Magidin >> >> Seems like these three conditions alone are enough to ensure S is a >> group: Define f : S --> S^S by f(x)(y) = xy. By (iii), for every x in >> S f(x) is one-to-one. By (ii), for every x in S f(x) maps S onto S. > > I'm sorry, but how do you get that? > > Saying that f(x) maps S onto S is saying that for all z there exists y > such that z=xy. But what we have is the *other* condition: for all z, > there exists y such that z = yx: (ii) specifies that you can always > solve equations *on the left*, not on the right. > > Am I missing something? > > If you know that f(x) is onto for every x, then you know that for all > a and b, there exists c such that a = bc. This gives that you can > solve all equations of the form a = bx; and (ii) gives that you can > solve all equations of the form a=yb; and these two together give that > you have a group, yes. But how do you know that f(x) is onto for every > x? > > -- > Arturo Magidin Oops, sorry, I misread your condition (ii), and the argument I gave just shows (with a few minor changes) that (i), (iii), and (ii') for all x and y there is z so that x = yz are enough to imply S is a group. Probably you knew that already. Give me a moment to wipe some egg off my face. My apologies for the erroneous and misleading post. Robert E. Beaudoin
From: Robert E. Beaudoin on 10 Jun 2010 10:09 On 06/10/10 01:18, Robert E. Beaudoin wrote: > On 06/09/10 12:21, Arturo Magidin wrote: >> On Jun 8, 11:45 pm, "Robert E. Beaudoin" <rbeaud...(a)acm.org> wrote: >>> On 06/08/10 16:17, Arturo Magidin wrote: >>> >>> >>> >>>> On Jun 2, 11:30 pm, Arturo Magidin <magi...(a)member.ams.org> wrote: >>> >>>> Not a full answer yet. >>> >>>> So, to recap: suppose you have a [nonempty] set S and a binary >>>> operation (which we denote by concatenation) on S such that >>> >>>> (i) the operation is associative; >>>> (ii) for every x and y in S, there exists z such that x = zy; >>>> (iii) For every r,s,t in S, if rs = rt, then s=t. >>> >>>> Will S be a group? >>> >>>> I'm pretty sure the answer is "no" in general, but I asked a >>>> colleague. He did point out that under some mild conditions, the >>>> answer is "yes": S will be a group if any of the following hold: >>> >>>> (a) S contains an idempotent; >>>> (b) every cyclic subsemigroup of S is finite; >>>> (c) there is at least one cyclic subsemigroup of S that is finite; >>>> (d) S is finite. >>> >>>> To see this, note that (d)->(c)->(b)->(a). Under condition (a), let e >>>> be an idempotent. Then for all x in S, eex = ex, so by left >>>> cancellation we have that ex=x for all x. Then from (ii) we get that >>>> for every x there exists z such that zx=e, and we have both left >>>> identity and left inverses, hence a group. >>> >>>> -- >>>> Arturo Magidin >>> >>> Seems like these three conditions alone are enough to ensure S is a >>> group: Define f : S --> S^S by f(x)(y) = xy. By (iii), for every x in >>> S f(x) is one-to-one. By (ii), for every x in S f(x) maps S onto S. >> >> I'm sorry, but how do you get that? >> >> Saying that f(x) maps S onto S is saying that for all z there exists y >> such that z=xy. But what we have is the *other* condition: for all z, >> there exists y such that z = yx: (ii) specifies that you can always >> solve equations *on the left*, not on the right. >> >> Am I missing something? >> >> If you know that f(x) is onto for every x, then you know that for all >> a and b, there exists c such that a = bc. This gives that you can >> solve all equations of the form a = bx; and (ii) gives that you can >> solve all equations of the form a=yb; and these two together give that >> you have a group, yes. But how do you know that f(x) is onto for every >> x? >> >> -- >> Arturo Magidin > > > Oops, sorry, I misread your condition (ii), and the argument I gave just > shows (with a few minor changes) that (i), (iii), and > > (ii') for all x and y there is z so that x = yz > > are enough to imply S is a group. Probably you knew that already. Give > me a moment to wipe some egg off my face. > > My apologies for the erroneous and misleading post. > > Robert E. Beaudoin > Well, I've got to stop posting at 1 AM. Sorry (again) for replying to myself, but now I see that I'm mistaken in the above post as well: (i), (ii'), and (iii) are not enough to imply S is a group. For a counterexample take S = {a, b} (with a and b distinct) with multiplication given by xy = y for all x and y in S. Your original question (with (i), (ii), and (iii)) I still can't settle one way or the other. R. Beaudoin
From: herbzet on 10 Jun 2010 13:19 herbzet wrote: > George Greene wrote: > > The original problem is arguably mis-phrased (in the book). > > What you ACTUALLY want to prove is NOT > > > a = a.c |= c = c.c > > BUT RATHER > > Aac[ a=a.c --> c=c.c ] Taken this way (and it seems reasonable to take it this way) then I don't think the group axioms are needed at all (and neither is the author's "Hint") -- it's just a FOL validity: just let a be c. The group axioms are just a distraction. This was actually my first thought after Frederick Williams reminded us of what '|=' means (one of the meanings, anyway). Every structure in which Aac[a=a.c] holds is a structure in which Ac[c=c.c]. I'm *agreeing* with you that the book phrasing seems unclear, given only what was in the post. After a week, it was still bothering me, so now it's off my chest. > > The fact that the original is stated withOUT quantifiers really > > is problematic unless the book has a convention regarding > > how they ought to be put back in. -- hz
From: Arturo Magidin on 10 Jun 2010 14:50 On Jun 8, 5:22 pm, herbzet <herb...(a)gmail.com> wrote: > > So, to recap: suppose you have a [nonempty] set S and a binary > > operation (which we denote by concatenation) on S such that > > > (i) the operation is associative; > > (ii) for every x and y in S, there exists z such that x = zy; > > (iii) For every r,s,t in S, if rs = rt, then s=t. > > > Will S be a group? > > > I'm pretty sure the answer is "no" in general, but I asked a > > colleague. [...] Indeed, the answer is "no". I was close to the following counterexample, but I kept trying to throw in all the bijections which was messing me up. The counterexample is called the Baer-Levi semigroup; they are dealt with in detail in Clifford and Preston's "The Algebraic Theory of Semigroups", volume II, pages 82-86. Let X be a denumerable (countably infinite) set. Let S be the semigroup, under composition, of all one-to-one maps f:X-->X such that X-f(X) is infinite. It is straightforward that this is not a group. It is also straightforward that this semigroup satisfies left cancellation, since in general one-to-one set-maps can be cancelled on the left. So it only remains to show that for all a and b in S, there exists f such that a=fb. Let a and b in S be given, and let y in X. If y is in b(X), say y = b(x), then let f(y) = f(b(x)) = a(x). Now, to define y in X - b(X), let h be any one-to-one map from X-b(X) to X-a(X) with the property that (X-a(X)) - h(X-b(X)) is infinite. If y is in X-b(X), then define f(y) = h(y). Then f is one-to-one, X-f(X) is infinite, and a = fb. Thus, S is a semigroup, not a group, that satisfies the desired condition. -- Arturo Magidin
From: herbzet on 10 Jun 2010 16:51 Arturo Magidin wrote: > herbzet wrote: > > > > So, to recap: suppose you have a [nonempty] set S and a binary > > > operation (which we denote by concatenation) on S such that > > > > > (i) the operation is associative; > > > (ii) for every x and y in S, there exists z such that x = zy; > > > (iii) For every r,s,t in S, if rs = rt, then s=t. > > > > > Will S be a group? > > > > > I'm pretty sure the answer is "no" in general, but I asked a > > > colleague. > > [...] > > Indeed, the answer is "no". I was close to the following > counterexample, but I kept trying to throw in all the bijections which > was messing me up. > > The counterexample is called the Baer-Levi semigroup; they are dealt > with in detail in Clifford and Preston's "The Algebraic Theory of > Semigroups", volume II, pages 82-86. > > Let X be a denumerable (countably infinite) set. Let S be the > semigroup, under composition, of all one-to-one maps f:X-->X such that > X-f(X) is infinite. It is straightforward that this is not a group. It > is also straightforward that this semigroup satisfies left > cancellation, since in general one-to-one set-maps can be cancelled on > the left. > > So it only remains to show that for all a and b in S, there exists f > such that a=fb. Let a and b in S be given, and let y in X. > > If y is in b(X), say y = b(x), then let f(y) = f(b(x)) = a(x). > > Now, to define y in X - b(X), let h be any one-to-one map from X-b(X) > to X-a(X) with the property that (X-a(X)) - h(X-b(X)) is infinite. > > If y is in X-b(X), then define f(y) = h(y). > > Then f is one-to-one, X-f(X) is infinite, and a = fb. > > Thus, S is a semigroup, not a group, that satisfies the desired > condition. My goodness! Thanx very much for following up on my rather off-the-cuff remark! -- hz
First
|
Prev
|
Pages: 1 2 3 4 5 Prev: Help with a question - throey of groups using functions Next: Theory of groups with functions - Help on a question |