Prev: geometry precisely defining ellipsis and how infinity is in the midsection #427 Correcting Math
Next: Accounting for Governmental and Nonprofit Entities, 15th Edition Earl Wilson McGraw Hill Test bank is available at affordable prices. Email me at allsolutionmanuals11[at]gmail.com if you need to buy this. All emails will be answered ASAP.
From: Jesse F. Hughes on 30 Mar 2010 09:04 Newberry <newberryxy(a)gmail.com> writes: > Indeed. But if we leave out all the vacuous sentences we can still do > all the useful arithmetic as we know it. Although all the people on > this board believe that such sentences are true nobody argued that > they were useful. Aatu even said that they did not belong in ordinary > mathematical reasoning. Furthermore there is a reason to think that > they are neither true nor false. I cannot think of any good reason for > claiming that 1 + 1 = 2 is not true. You seem to have misrepresented Aatu's claims. Moreover, you're just wrong. I've argued repeatedly that some sentences of the form ~(Ex)(P & Q) occur in ordinary mathematical reasoning (and hence are useful), even when (Ex)P is false. An example occurred in sci.math recently. Simon C. Roberts gave a purported proof of FLT[1], by arguing: ~(En)(Ea,b,c)(a^n + b^n = c^n & a, b, c are pairwise coprime). Let's denote a^n + b^n = c^n by P(a,b,c,n) and a, b, c are pairwise coprime by Q(a,b,c), so that Simon's argument attempts to show that ~(En)(Ea,b,c)( P(a,b,c,n) & Q(a,b,c) ). (1) Of course, I am *not* claiming that he proved what he claims. That's beside my point. A poster named bill replied that (1) is not Fermat's last theorem[2], which has the form ~(En)(Ea,b,c) P(a,b,c,n). (2) Arturo responded[3] by proving (En)(Ea,b,c) P(a,b,c,n) -> (En)(Ea,b,c)( P(a,b,c,n) & Q(a,b,c) ). (3) Hence, a proof of (1) yields a proof of (2) by modus tollens. According to you, however, if (2) is true (and I assume we all know that (2) was proved by Wiles), then (1) is meaningless. Yet, no one here balked at the claim that (1) could be used to prove (2) (once (3) was proved). No one here had any trouble understanding what (1) means. Everyone in the thread accepted this form of mathematical argument as beyond suspicion -- although the claim that Simon actually proved (1) is regarded as doubtful. So, you're just plain wrong. These statements that you call meaningless occur in ordinary mathematical reasoning all the time. Footnotes: [1] Message id <1917288606.455209.1269716329839.JavaMail.root(a)gallium.mathforum.org>, in the thread "Another Proof of Fermats Last Theorem". [2] Message id <50f09d88-a96b-464c-aec5-be000f0be40d(a)x23g2000prd.googlegroups.com>. [3] Message id <e6768d43-7706-41f4-bff8-8e666d693c3a(a)j21g2000yqh.googlegroups.com>. -- "There's lots of things in this old world to take a poor boy down. If you leave them be, you can save yourself some pain. You don't have to live in fear, but you best have some respect, For rattlesnakes, painted ladies and cocaine." -- Bob Childers
From: Transfer Principle on 30 Mar 2010 15:42 On Mar 26, 9:55 am, MoeBlee <jazzm...(a)hotmail.com> wrote: > On Mar 26, 12:20 am, Transfer Principle <lwal...(a)lausd.net> wrote: > > proof of 0.999...=1 to which I linked explicitly lists the > > Replacement Schema as one of the axioms that is used > > in the proof. > Replacement isn't needed to prove .999... = 1. With David Ullrich's > help, I posted a rigorous proof (in Z-regularity) of .999... = 1 in a > thread for that purpose a few years ago. > That 1 is the multiplicative identity does not require replacement. As usual, I was unable to find Ullrich's proof via a Google search, but I did go back to the Metamath proof and find where the Replacement Schema was used. Let's begin by trying to proof that 1 is the multiplicative identity of N, in other words: AneN (n*1 = n) So we begin by noting that we are considering N to be the set of nonzero finite ordinals, omega\{0}. So we use the recursive definition of multiplication of ordinals to obtain: AneN (n*1 = n*0 + n) AneN (n*1 = 0 + n) But hold on a minute. Multiplication of ordinals is defined using transfinite recursion -- which requires the Replacement Schema! At this point, one might point out that we only need to define the operations on the _finite_ ordinals, and so we ought to use finite, rather than _trans_finite, recursion. But finite recursion -- though it apparently avoids Replacement Schema -- requires the Axiom of _Infinity_ in its proof. It may seem ironic that _finite_ recursion requires Infinity, yet _trans_finite recursion doesn't, but this is confimed at the following two links: http://us.metamath.org/mpegif/inf3.html http://us.metamath.org/mpegif/mmnotes2004.txt Thus, by using transfinite recursion rather than finite recursion, the Metamath proof of 1 as the multiplicative identity avoids the Axiom of Infinity. We know that mathematicians prefer parsimony with regards to the axioms used in a proof. So if T is a theory and phi is a axiom (that is undecidable in T), then given two proofs of a statement, one in T and the other in T+phi, the proof in T is usually preferable. If the proof in T is only slightly longer than the proof in T+phi, then the proof in T is still preferable. Only if the proof in T is significantly longer (say 10, or 100 times as long) than the proof in T+phi will mathematicians consider assuming phi to make the proof shorter. But what if there's a statement that's not provable in T, but we have a choice between two axioms (or schemata) to add to T in order to produce a proof? For "1 is the multiplicative identity" appears not to be provable in Z-Infinity (assuming it's consistent), but we can find a proof in either Z (using finite induction) or ZF-Infinity (using transfinite induction instead). Which proof is considered preferable? On one hand, the goal isn't to define N, but _R_. One can avoid Infinity when trying to prove "n*1 = n for all natural numbers," but good luck trying to prove "r*1 = r for all _real_ numbers" (or even anything else about _R_) in ZF-Infinity. Since we're going to use Infinity to define R anyway, there's no real point in avoiding the axiom when discussing the properties of N. Thus, it's better to give the proof avoiding Replacement Schema instead -- and this is exactly what MoeBlee and Ullrich did -- work in Z(-Regularity -- we already know how to avoid Regularity, so I won't keep writing "-Regularity" each time I refer to a theory). On the other hand, we already know that some so-called "cranks" and finitists don't work in ZF(C) -- and we already know that the majority of them find _Infinity_, not _Replacement_, objectionable. So in deference to the finitist, we ought to avoid Infinity in as many proofs as possible, even if it requires using other axioms and schemata such as Replacement. Thus, to such posters, the proof in ZF-Infinity would be preferable to the proof in Z. But of course, a(n ultra)finitist has no business even referring to 0.999... in the first place, unless to denote only _finitely_ many nines after the decimal point. A similar debate often occurs when discussing Q -- can a finitist or "crank" work with rational numbers? On one hand, rationals are often defined as equivalence classes of ordered pairs, so 1/2 would be defined as {(1,2), (2,4), (3,6), (4,8), ...} -- this is evidently an infinite set, so Infinity is necessary. But on the other hand, we can define rationals to be only a single ordered pair representing the lowest- terms fraction, so 1/2 would be defined as (1,2), which can be defined without the Axiom of Infinity. Metamath uses the former definition, for why should one have to keep dividing by the gcd of the numerator and denominator to get a fraction into lowest terms just to avoid Infinity, when the ultimate goal is to define not Q, but _R_, where we'd use Infinity anyway? But the finitist/"crank" trying to avoid Infinity at all costs will use the latter definition of rational number. Returning to N, since Metamath has already defined via transfinite recursion using Replacement, it might as well use it in its proof of "1 is the multiplicative identity" and all that. But MoeBlee and Ullrich were explicitly working in Z(-Regularity), and so they're going to use the construction of R that doesn't require transfinite induction or the Replacement Schema. I'm not sure whether MoeBlee and Ullrich wish to avoid Replacement in the same way that a finitist/"crank" wishes to avoid Infinity. It may be that MoeBlee and Ullrich are open to using Replacement when it is absolutely inevitable, but as long as they can avoid the schema -- and one can construct R without it -- they'll do so. (And in order to reduce my habit of lumping posters together, it could be that MoeBlee and Ullrich are divided on this issue -- perhaps one of them will use Replacement when it's necessary, and the other will avoid it like the plague, just as a finitist/"crank" avoids Infinity.) And therefore, even without finding MoeBlee's or Ullrich's proof, I can figure out what their proof is. We basically take the Metamath proof of "0.999...=1" and replace all instances of transfinite induction with finite induction. Then voila -- we'll have a proof of "0.999...=1" which doesn't require Replacement and thus works in Z(-Regularity). QED
From: Transfer Principle on 30 Mar 2010 15:57 On Mar 26, 10:04 am, MoeBlee <jazzm...(a)hotmail.com> wrote: > On Mar 26, 12:42 am, Transfer Principle <lwal...(a)lausd.net> wrote: > > as powerful > This cries for a definition or explanation of what is meant by 'as > powerful'. In mathematical logic we have various notions such as > 'intepretability' and 'conservative extension'. But some of your > comments seem not to use 'as powerful' in such technical senses > (otherwise some of your questions in this regard would be non- > starters). Marshall Spight was the first to use the phrase in this thread. I only use the phrase in reponse to Spight's post. Here is a quote from the post from earlier in this thread, back on the 2nd of March, at 4:11PM Greenwich time: "One thing that the cranks and crankophiles never understand is that the systems they come up with add a lot of complexity while actually removing functionality or utility. To do so merely to avoid some counterintuitive but harmless property (such as vacuous truth, in Newberry's case) is a huge waste of time. Less powerful; more work to use: that's a crank theory for you." So Spight criticizes so-called "crank" theories as less powerful than some other theory -- presumably the standard theory (ZFC). My goal, therefore, is to find a theory that's _as_ powerful as ZFC, so that Spight would have less reason to criticize it. In order for me to reduce my habit of misinterpreting other posters, it would be far better for Spight himself to state what exactly he meant when he wrote "less powerful." That way, we can agree on what criteria a theory needs to satisfy in order for it to be "as powerful" as ZFC, without "removing functionality or utility."
From: Transfer Principle on 30 Mar 2010 16:29 On Mar 27, 7:02 am, "Tim Golden BandTech.com" <tttppp...(a)yahoo.com> wrote: > On Mar 26, 5:55 pm, Nam Nguyen <namducngu...(a)shaw.ca> wrote: > > Any rate, enough talk. Do you have even a single absolute truth you > > could show me so that I'd realize I've been wrong all along? Let's > > begin with the natural numbers: which formula in the language of > > arithmetic could _you_ demonstrate as absolutely true? > There is a fairly straightforward construction that can yield both > boolean logic and continuous higher forms, and even a lower form that > I will call universal. > Constrain the real numbers to those values whose magnitude is unity. > We see two options > +1, -1 . > Using polysign numbers extend this system to P3. Ah yes, the polysign numbers. I still remember Golden's constuction of these sets. > One might initially consider there to be a three verticed logic here, > but in the general form we see that the unity values now form a > continuous circle. There was a discussion of alternate-valued logic back when tommy1729 proposed using three-valued logic (tommy1729 being, of course, one of Golden's biggest supporters). But we found out that usually, standard theorists object to these alternate forms of logic. For one thing, standard theorists obviously accept two-valued Boolean logic (FOL), and they appear to be open to continuum-valued logic (also called "fuzzy" logic). But they tend to object to kappa-valued logic, where kappa is a cardinal that is strictly between two and the cardinality of the continuum. > In two dimensions we see that the same procedure yields a continuum of > values, though there are arguably those three unique positions > -1, +1, *1 . But notice that Golden does acknowledge a continuum of values. So perhaps this could be a form of fuzzy logic that the standard theorists might accept as well. There's a huge difference between fuzzy logic and Golden's though. For fuzzy logic usually considers the values to lie in the interval [0,1], with 0 being false and 1 being true. Golden's fuzzy logic is decidedly _not_ described by the interval [0,1] at all. Golden regularly points out that multiplication on the set {-1,+1,*1} in P3 is isomorphic to addition in the group Z/3Z. In general, Golden wishes to construct an n-valued logic by considering a subset of Pn that's isomorphic to addition in the group Z/nZ, which is also isomorphic to the multiplicative set of nth roots of unity in C. (As was discussed in many previous Golden threads, _addition_ in Pn is not isomorphic to _addition_ in C, but this current subthread only deals with multiplication, not addition.) Thus, our continuum-valued logic can be described by the entire unit circle in C, not the unit interval [0,1]. Now we ask ourselves, is such a logic even possible. Back in the tommy1729 three-valued logic threads, the standard theorists often pointed out that what they needed to see were the laws of inference for any proposed logic. Without laws of inference, one can't really call it a logic at all. I wouldn't mind taking at the laws of inference for fuzzy logic and modifying them so that they work for Golden's logic. But of course, I don't own a textbook on fuzzy logic or its laws of inference, nor do I plan on owning such a book anytime soon. > By leaving the Euclidean and working the sphere these forms exist > naturally. Hmmm, non-Euclidean geometry and the sphere. This reminds me of AP's work as well. I wonder whether the AP-adics might work better if we used Golden's logic instead of FOL. (And before Jesse Hughes or anyone else protests, I'm fully aware that the link between Golden's post here and AP's work is even flimsier than that between Newberry and Clarke. I'm the one who's trying to unify the so-called "cranks" as best as I can in order to find a theory that will satisfy at least two of them, which saves me work from having to find a different theory for each and every "crank.")
From: Jesse F. Hughes on 30 Mar 2010 18:02 Transfer Principle <lwalke3(a)lausd.net> writes: > There was a discussion of alternate-valued logic back when tommy1729 > proposed using three-valued logic (tommy1729 being, of course, one > of Golden's biggest supporters). But we found out that usually, > standard theorists object to these alternate forms of logic. No, you found no such thing. Multi-valued logic is a perfectly respectable field. (It does not follow that Tommy's blatherings are perfectly respectable. I don't read Timothy's posts, so I don't offer an opinion on them. They might be blatherings, too, for all I know.) Of course, most mathematicians would bristle at the suggestion that they ought to do their work in three-valued logic. But that's not the same as objecting to three-valued logic per se. -- Jesse F. Hughes "Radicals are interesting because they were considered 'radical' by the people who played with them who wrote a lot of math work that modern mathematics depends on." --Another JSH history lesson
First
|
Prev
|
Next
|
Last
Pages: 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 Prev: geometry precisely defining ellipsis and how infinity is in the midsection #427 Correcting Math Next: Accounting for Governmental and Nonprofit Entities, 15th Edition Earl Wilson McGraw Hill Test bank is available at affordable prices. Email me at allsolutionmanuals11[at]gmail.com if you need to buy this. All emails will be answered ASAP. |