Prev: geometry precisely defining ellipsis and how infinity is in the midsection #427 Correcting Math
Next: Accounting for Governmental and Nonprofit Entities, 15th Edition Earl Wilson McGraw Hill Test bank is available at affordable prices. Email me at allsolutionmanuals11[at]gmail.com if you need to buy this. All emails will be answered ASAP.
From: Nam Nguyen on 3 Apr 2010 11:39 Daryl McCullough wrote: > Newberry says... > >> If it absolutely certain that PA is consistent why don't we formalize >> the reasoning? > > It has been. It's easily formalized in ZFC. But PA's consistency itself and the proof of PA's consistency in ZFC are 2 different and independent issues. (There's a chance ZFC could be syntactically inconsistent and in which case it'd prove anything).
From: Nam Nguyen on 3 Apr 2010 12:09 Newberry wrote: > On Apr 2, 7:00 am, Nam Nguyen <namducngu...(a)shaw.ca> wrote: >> Daryl McCullough wrote: >>> Newberry says... >>>> On Apr 1, 5:59=A0am, Aatu Koskensilta <aatu.koskensi...(a)uta.fi> wrote: >>>>> How do I know that Peano arithmetic is consistent? I know it the way I >>>>> know any mathematical theorem I have personally proved. >>>> You proved PA consistent? >>> It's easy to prove in ZF. >> Is ZF _syntactically_ consistent? > > Such a proof in ZF that PA is consistent is obviously wothless. We had > a long discussion about this a while ago. Ultimately inconsistency proof is just 1st order _syntactical & finite_ proof, while consistency is neither syntactical nor finite: it's a meta proof requiring knowledge of FOL, subjective intuitions about "truth", about the natural numbers, or all of those. But in pursuing consistency proof in general, we tend not to realize a *subtle* relationship between intuition, truth, and syntactical proof. We often say a formula is a theorem iff there's a "finite" proof for it. But that isn't quite precise; it should be: "iff there's a _non-zero_ finite proof for it"! The distinction is necessary because intuition would still accept the following scenarios as valid: 1. - There's a proof which is of non-zero finite length. (This would be a typical proof). 2. - All proofs are of the zero finite length. This would correspond to to there's no proof! 3. - There's no proof of non-zero finite length length, but intuition might perceive a proof of infinite length! This is a enigma in reasoning: on the one hand intuition could have reason to believe the underlying concept _might be_ sound, but on the other hand neither the concept or its negation can be a syntactical theorem of FOL! So, if a "proof" falls into the 3rd category, the underlying formula would be neither true nor false, model-theoretically speaking or otherwise! And non-relative consistency "proofs" would fall into this 3rd category.
From: Newberry on 3 Apr 2010 12:42 On Apr 2, 3:19 am, stevendaryl3...(a)yahoo.com (Daryl McCullough) wrote: > Newberry says... > > > > >On Mar 31, 5:12=A0am, stevendaryl3...(a)yahoo.com (Daryl McCullough) > >wrote: > >> In general, any *procedure* used to evaluate the truth of sentences > >> in a self-referential language is incomplete, in the sense that there > >> are true sentences that are not evaluated as true by the procedure. > > >> This is easy to see: Let P be some procedure to evaluate the truth > >> of sentences. Then consider the sentence > > >> "When procedure P is applied to this sentence, the result is not true" > > >And what procedure would it be? > > Well, for example, the search for a proof for the statement. Or > Gaifman's procedure. > > >It cannot be Gaifman's procedure because the sentence above does > >not have the form "The sentence written in/on ... is true" > > Then, as I said, it's a true sentence that Gaifman's procedure does > not return true for. Gaifman's procedure is not applicable. It cannot take your sentence as an argument. > > -- > Daryl McCullough > Ithaca, NY
From: Newberry on 3 Apr 2010 12:49 On Apr 3, 6:54 am, stevendaryl3...(a)yahoo.com (Daryl McCullough) wrote: > Newberry says... > > >If it absolutely certain that PA is consistent why don't we formalize > >the reasoning? > > It has been. It's easily formalized in ZFC. I do not know why we are going through this circle again. Look it is very simple. All you have to do is to divorce ~(Ex)(Ey)(Pxy & Qy) (1) from ~(Ex)Pxm (2) [No need to repeat that m is the Goedel number of (1).] Then there is no reason why (2) could not be proven. > -- > Daryl McCullough > Ithaca, NY
From: Daryl McCullough on 3 Apr 2010 12:51 Newberry says... > >On Apr 3, 6:54=A0am, stevendaryl3...(a)yahoo.com (Daryl McCullough) wrote: >> Newberry says... >> >> >If it absolutely certain that PA is consistent why don't we formalize >> >the reasoning? >> >> It has been. It's easily formalized in ZFC. > >I do not know why we are going through this circle again. > >Look it is very simple. All you have to do is to divorce > >~(Ex)(Ey)(Pxy & Qy) (1) > >from > >~(Ex)Pxm (2) > >[No need to repeat that m is the Goedel number of (1).] Then there is >no reason why (2) could not be proven. It can be proven. Just not in PA. -- Daryl McCullough Ithaca, NY
First
|
Prev
|
Next
|
Last
Pages: 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 Prev: geometry precisely defining ellipsis and how infinity is in the midsection #427 Correcting Math Next: Accounting for Governmental and Nonprofit Entities, 15th Edition Earl Wilson McGraw Hill Test bank is available at affordable prices. Email me at allsolutionmanuals11[at]gmail.com if you need to buy this. All emails will be answered ASAP. |