Prev: geometry precisely defining ellipsis and how infinity is in the midsection #427 Correcting Math
Next: Accounting for Governmental and Nonprofit Entities, 15th Edition Earl Wilson McGraw Hill Test bank is available at affordable prices. Email me at allsolutionmanuals11[at]gmail.com if you need to buy this. All emails will be answered ASAP.
From: Daryl McCullough on 5 Apr 2010 06:56 Newberry says... >On Apr 3, 9:51=A0am, stevendaryl3...(a)yahoo.com (Daryl McCullough) wrote: >> It [the Godel statement for PA] can be proven. Just not in PA. > >Cool. So we know that the search for a proof of Goedel's sentence will >never terminate. Can we apply this knowledge to Diophantine equations? The Godel sentence is equivalent to the claim that a certain Diophantine equation has no solutions. So yes. -- Daryl McCullough Ithaca, NY
From: Nam Nguyen on 5 Apr 2010 22:15 Marshall wrote: > On Apr 4, 10:08 pm, Nam Nguyen <namducngu...(a)shaw.ca> wrote: >> Marshall wrote: >>> On Apr 4, 9:33 am, Nam Nguyen <namducngu...(a)shaw.ca> wrote: >>>> Marshall wrote: >>>>> On Apr 2, 5:32 pm, Nam Nguyen <namducngu...(a)shaw.ca> wrote: >>>>>> Let me put to rest the idea we know enough about the natural numbers, >>>>>> to prove important thing such as the consistency of PA. I'll do that >>>>>> by pointing out the existence of a specific unknown natural number. >>>>> Why do you think the existence of a specific unknown number >>>>> should have anything to do with consistency? >>>> Because they (the syntactical proof of consistency and collectively >>>> many formulas about this unknown natural) both connote the same thing >>>> in meta level: impossibility of syntactical proof. If you can't prove >>>> a certain formula related to this number, you can forget about proving >>>> a consistency, syntactically speaking. >>> Both of these sentences are just a restatement of the position that >>> I asked you for support of. My question is not, do you consider >>> a proof of consistency of PA and the existence of an unknown natural >>> number to be mutually incompatible. You have clearly stated so. >> Huh? I'm not quite following you here. First of, you clearly asked me >> why the existence of a specific unknown natural number "should have >> anything to do with consistency [proof]". And I gave you an answer for >> that: their both connoting an "impossibility of [some] syntactical proof" >> would be their "having anything to do" with each other. >> >> That's all I said here. And I didn't state anything about them being >> "mutually incompatible" or what not! > > OK. So you mean that the two things have "something" to do > with each other, but it's just a connotation, not any kind of > logical result. But look at the connotation: "impossibility of [some] syntactical proof". Such an impossibility must have impact on logical reasoning and results, don't you think? >>> Rather, my question is WHY do you see them as mutually >>> incompatible. >> Again where did I even hint these 2 are "mutually incompatible"? > > When you said "If you can't prove a certain formula related to this > number, you can forget about proving a consistency" I took that to > mean that being unable to prove a certain formula is incompatible > with a consistency proof. My mistake. > > Apparently what you are saying is that "you can forget about > proving a consistency" but at the same time, proving consistency > is still compatible. I guess I don't really understand that. But where did I state anything like "proving consistency is still compatible"? In fact, "compatible" with what? I'm not sure I understand what the complaint here be. >> I think I already did: they both connote impossibility of some >> syntactical proofs. So we just pick one as a representation >> (an epitome so to speak) of the other. > > I have no idea what this is supposed to mean. It's akin to an equivalence class having 2 elements: you could choose one of them as a representation of the other. >>> As far as I am aware, you have not given the conditions under >>> which you would consider the consistency of a theory to be >>> proven. >> You're correct that I haven't, and I never will: because the conditions >> would be impossible to be met. That doesn't mean the following isn't >> a standard definition of syntactical consistency that you and I and >> everyone else would accept: >> >> consistency <-> not being syntactically inconsistent. > > So you are saying that no theory can ever be proven to be > consistent. That's correct. That's to say if you meant _syntactically_ consistent. > (Also, how do you expect to convince me that > the conditions for a consistency proof are impossible to > meet without telling me what those conditions are?) You yourself should be convinced: because the rules of inference doesn't have any provision to dis-prove a non-theorem, which would be needed to show the negation of syntactical inconsistency (i.e. consistency). > Would you agree that this position is not one for which > there is any mainstream acceptance? My agreement or disagreement is irrelevant here: we should go strictly by definitions of consistency, inconsistency, and of rules of inference. And the definition of rules of inference will not permit a proof of _syntactical_ consistency. > > What about the theory with no axioms; is it impossible to prove > that it is consistent? The assumed reasoning framework here is FOL=. So all theories have at least one axiom! In any rate, syntactically you can't use rules of inference to prove consistency, as explained above. > If it's not consistent, or not possible to > prove it is consistent, what mechanism might admit an > inconsistency? As having been explained, an inconsistency proof would be merely a finite syntactical proof. > Surely it is not a logical conflict between > some of its axioms? Are you then saying that FOL itself > is not known to be consistent? What about propositional > logic; is it possible to prove it consistent? What about > boolean algebra? Inconsistency and inconsistency here are meant to be of FOL formal systems. If we're not talking about formal systems then we're not talking about any other kind of "(in)consistency" in this context. (At least I'm not). So, for example, is your mentioned "boolean algebra" a formal system? >>> As far as proving INconsistency, I was not under the >>> impression that you disagreed with the usual method of >>> deriving a contradiction. >> That's correct that I've never disagreed: because the method of proving >> inconsistency is just a _finite FOL proof_, as I mentioned quite a few >> times here and elsewhere. > > And what if someone proved that a FOL proof of inconsistency > for some particular theory is impossible? No one can prove it's impossible to prove a formal system's inconsistency: if it's inconsistent, it's provable (in principle at least). > Or are you saying > that it is impossible to prove that something is > impossible to prove? I'm not sure if I had actually said that. The point I've said is we can't prove syntactical consistency of a formal system via rules of inference. > If so, how do you know? Did you prove it? > If you didn't, then how can you claim to know? If you did, I see > a logical problem with your position. > > > Marshall
From: Nam Nguyen on 10 Apr 2010 00:46 Nam Nguyen wrote: > Jim Burns wrote: > >> I think it would be very useful to me in understanding >> what you are trying to accomplish if you were >> to give a summary of the best arguments AGAINST your >> positions. > > As promised I'll summarize what I think as the best arguments > against my positions. > *** > > Imho, the 3 major and best arguments against my belief, that the > nature of FOL reasoning is that of relativity or of being subjective, > are the following objections: > > (O1) The Universality Objection: > > In this objection, the correctness in reasoning under one logical > framework should be _universally constant_ and shouldn't be a > function of individual subjective beliefs or knowledge. My claiming > on the relativity nature of FOL reasoning seems to violate this > natural and unobjectionable, say, "sanctity". > > (O2) The Philosophy Objection: > > In this objection, the ideas such that there are formulas written > in the language of arithmetic that can be neither arithmetically > true nor false are just philosophical ideas and thus can't be a > basis to attack the current FOL reasoning. > > (O3) The Ordinary Mathematics Objection: > > This objection seems to be a cross-breed between O1 and O2. In this > objection, FOL reasoning is build upon the ordinary mathematical > knowledge that *in principle* should be universally _self evident_ > to all who are trained or study mathematics. As such FOL reasoning > should be universally the same and should _not_ be subjective or > relativistic. > > Again, these are only my thoughts of what the arguments against my position > be. It would certainly be helpful if those who oppose my position could > further clarify in technical clarity what they perceive are problems in my > positions. I also don't mind in subsequent posts to further defend my > position or to provide more counter-arguments. I'm still hoping to hear some responses, from Jim, my opponents, or from anyone.
From: David Bernier on 10 Apr 2010 05:01 Nam Nguyen wrote: > Nam Nguyen wrote: >> Jim Burns wrote: >> >>> I think it would be very useful to me in understanding >>> what you are trying to accomplish if you were >>> to give a summary of the best arguments AGAINST your >>> positions. >> >> As promised I'll summarize what I think as the best arguments >> against my positions. > >> *** >> >> Imho, the 3 major and best arguments against my belief, that the >> nature of FOL reasoning is that of relativity or of being subjective, >> are the following objections: >> >> (O1) The Universality Objection: >> >> In this objection, the correctness in reasoning under one logical >> framework should be _universally constant_ and shouldn't be a >> function of individual subjective beliefs or knowledge. My claiming >> on the relativity nature of FOL reasoning seems to violate this >> natural and unobjectionable, say, "sanctity". >> >> (O2) The Philosophy Objection: >> >> In this objection, the ideas such that there are formulas written >> in the language of arithmetic that can be neither arithmetically >> true nor false are just philosophical ideas and thus can't be a >> basis to attack the current FOL reasoning. >> >> (O3) The Ordinary Mathematics Objection: >> >> This objection seems to be a cross-breed between O1 and O2. In this >> objection, FOL reasoning is build upon the ordinary mathematical >> knowledge that *in principle* should be universally _self evident_ >> to all who are trained or study mathematics. As such FOL reasoning >> should be universally the same and should _not_ be subjective or >> relativistic. >> >> Again, these are only my thoughts of what the arguments against my >> position >> be. It would certainly be helpful if those who oppose my position could >> further clarify in technical clarity what they perceive are problems >> in my >> positions. I also don't mind in subsequent posts to further defend my >> position or to provide more counter-arguments. > > I'm still hoping to hear some responses, from Jim, my opponents, or from > anyone. In a proof by contradiction, we assume the negation of what we want to prove (i.e. not(P) ). Then, with that assumption, we arrive at "G .and. not(G)" . This is done in an "imaginary world" where P is false. Because we followed logic, and arrived at "G .and. not(G)", we conclude that not(P) is false. So P is true. Do you see problems with starting with a false premise, not(P) ? By the way, I don't remember hearing of the philosopher P. F. Strawson before this or a related thread. Wikipedia on philosopher P. F. Strawson < http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/P._F._Strawson > . David Bernier
From: John Jones on 10 Apr 2010 05:18 Newberry wrote: > I had claimed that if for all a in the range of x > > (y)Aay (1) > > is vacuously true then > > (x)(y)Aay (2) > > is vacuously true. I have got an objection that this is scope fallacy > and that the inference is incorrect. I do not know, but I no longer > claim that (2) is vacuously true. I do claim that if for all a in the > range of x > > (y)Aay (1) > > is neither true nor false then > > (x)(y)Aay (2) > > is neither true nor false. A new version of my paper titled 'When Are > Relations Neither True Nor False?' is posted here > http://www.scribd.com/doc/26833131/RelationsAndPresuppositions-2010-02-13. > > Note that given > > ~(Ex)(Ey)[(x + y < 6) & (y = 8)] > > in Strawson's logic of presuppositions the formula is neither true nor > false for any choice of y. Let y be 8: > > ~(Ex)[(x + 8 < 6) & (8 = 8)] > i.e. > (x)[(x + 8 < 6) -> ~(8 = 8)] > > the subject class is empty and hence the sentence is neither true nor > false. > > Let y be anything but 8, say 9: > > ~(Ex)[(x + 9 < 6) & (9 = 8)] > i.e. > (x)[(9 = 8) -> ~(x + 9 < 6)] > > the subject class is empty and hence the sentence is neither true nor > false. > > Comments appreciated. Why don't you give an example? An example of a relationship that is neither true nor false is "Encore, Encore!" or "I promise", etc. If we are real mathematicians, and mathematics represents reality, how would you express these phrases in mathematical syntax? Other examples which aren't performatives are any statement whatever: It would first help to lay out what it is for something to be true or false. For a proposition to be true or false, we must show that there is an alternative proposition to that stated. But we can't assume that there is an alternative.
First
|
Prev
|
Next
|
Last
Pages: 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 Prev: geometry precisely defining ellipsis and how infinity is in the midsection #427 Correcting Math Next: Accounting for Governmental and Nonprofit Entities, 15th Edition Earl Wilson McGraw Hill Test bank is available at affordable prices. Email me at allsolutionmanuals11[at]gmail.com if you need to buy this. All emails will be answered ASAP. |