From: Tony Orlow on
Lester Zick wrote:
> On Tue, 24 Apr 2007 09:27:05 -0400, Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com>
> wrote:
>
>>>> The "truth" of the two truth values is that I've declared them a priori
>>>> as the two alternative evaluations for the truth of a statement.
>>> Well there are two difficulties here, Tony. You declare two a priori
>>> alternatives but how do you know they are in fact alternatives? In
>>> other words what mechanism causes them to alternate from one to the
>>> other? It looks to me like what you actually mean is that you declare
>>> two values 1 and 0 having nothing in particular to do with "truth" or
>>> anything except 1 and 0.
>> 1=not(0)
>> 0=not(1)
>> x<>not(x)
>>
>> That says it all. "not" defines the relationship between 0 and 1. In
>> arithmetic terms, not(x) can be equated with 1-x, for obvious intuitive
>> reasons. If 1 is the universe, and x is some portion of that universe,
>> everything that is not(x) is everything in the universe, minus what's in x.
>>
>> "not not" then equates to 1-(1-x), which is just x, which doesn't have
>> any truth value until you assign it one.
>
> Okay, Tony. Basically you're agreeing with what I've been saying. But
> I'm still bothered by this binary arithmetic approach to the mechanics
> of "not" and "not" compounded in terms of itself.

not(means_anything(without("not",predicate)))

not(x) is a one-place logical operator. Without a predicate x, and a
truth value for that predicate, "not" doesn't have a truth value. "Not"
simply negates itself into oblivion.

>
> I think you really need a symbolic rather than arithmetic approach to
> the problem. In other words you've got the idea of differences but the
> differences are not between binary logic values. They're taken between
> real things in logical terms which can result in any and all kinds of
> differences any and all of which can be regurgitated tautologically in
> terms of subsequent differences. The 0 stays but the binary 1 goes. We
> can't just take the truth of one set of circumstances and compare it
> to the truth of another set of circumstances. Both sets may be true
> but may be true in different ways which preclude analyzing the truth
> of both together in exactly common terms.

That depends how well you analyze what you're talking about. For all
intents and purposes, there is some finite number of differences
required to distinguish any object from any other, if nothing else,
limited by our ability to distinguish things. For any of those
differences, some finite specification suffices to determine them, or
they are not different in that respect. But, that's all on a pre-logical
level.

>
> This is why I analyze the problem in terms of predicate combinations
> and not in strictly binary terms. We might have a "large apple" and a
> "green apple" both of which predicate combinations could be true of
> one specific real object without having any common "truth value" in
> terms of each other. This is why I analyze the problem in symbolic
> terms rather than strictly binary terms of common truth values.
>
> ~v~~

Okay, sure. We can have an apple A, and we may have green(A) or
not(green(A)), and we may have large(A) or not(large(A)). So, as far as
greenness and largeness, we have four possibilities.

We may relate the two attributes probabilistically, and say most green
apples are little, and many little apples are green, and many red apples
are large, and many large apples are red, in whatever proportions
between 0 and 1. If those proportions are all 50%, there's no
correlation. In any case, all the mutually exclusive colors of apples
add to all the apples, and all the mutually exclusive sizes of apples
add to all the apples.

01oo
From: Tony Orlow on
Lester Zick wrote:
> On Tue, 24 Apr 2007 09:27:05 -0400, Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com>
> wrote:
>
>>> The second problem is what makes you think two "truth" alternatives
>>> you declare are exhaustive? This is related to the first difficulty.
>>> You can certainly assume one thing or alternative a priori but not
>>> two. And without some mechanism to produce the second from the first
>>> and in turn the first from the second exclusively you just wind up
>>> with an non mechanical dualism where there is no demonstration the two
>>> are in fact alternatives at all or exhaustive alternatives either.
>> See the mechanism for their mutual definition, above.
>>
>> As far as the two truth values being "exhaustive", it's simply declared
>> in Boolean logic that these are the only two values allowed, true() and
>> false(). Now, these are not really all the possibilities, if one looks
>> at truth in the context of probability. Where a probability of truth of
>> x is 100%, the truth value is 1, meaning "definitely true". Where a
>> statement has a 0% probability of truth, the value is 0, meaning
>> "definitely false". Between these two lie a continuous set of possible
>> probabilities. So, in this context, {0,1} is NOT an exhaustive set of
>> all alternatives. But, this requires that you accept partial truth,
>> which doesn't seem to be acceptable for you. What other alternatives do
>> you see besides true(x) and false(x) for a statement x?
>
> Well as noted in the preceeding reply segment there are certain subtle
> complexities in relations between true predicate combinations which
> obscure the idea of binary truth values but have nothing to do with
> probabilities whatsoever. I don't reject the idea of probability but I
> think the idea of truth in general has to be straightened out before
> we can get to any mechanically exact understanding of probability.
>
> I agree the common boolean notion of truth only allows for two truth
> values but I don't agree that actually reflects what truth means in
> strict mechanical terms.

You mean determining the truth of any given statement? You have to see
under what conditions it holds.

>
> Taking two symbolic predicate combinations such as "green apple" and
> "large apple" both of which are true of one specific real thing we are
> then left to consider the truth of each in relation to the other. And
> what we find are that there are complex subordinated differences
> between them not represented in simple binary 1's. It's a sequential
> combinatorial logic problem where the truth of each predicate has to
> be considered individually and in combination.

Okay, so you're talking about what I mentioned in my last post, the
relationship between "green" and "large" in relation to "apple". This
involves the probabilistic approach, I think. One might say that 10% of
large apples are green, so green(large(apple))=0.1 and
not(green(large(apple)))=0.9. You might say 99% of green apples are not
large, so large(green(apple)) would be 0.01 and not(large(green(apple)))
is 0.99. You might then be able to say that, given that an apple is
large or not, that the "truth" of it being green is 0.1.

>
> Let's suppose for example we have two predicates "animal" and "fox"
> both of which are true with respect to one specific real thing. And we
> represent the truth of each with a binary 1. Then we further consider
> the truth of the predicates in combination and we can't tell whether
> the thing is an "animal fox" or a "fox animal" from the representation
> of truth in each instance. Thus the binary arithmetic representation
> is completely misleading even though it correctly identifies the truth
> in each instance. It just can't tell us how the true but different
> predicates "fox" and "animal" relate to each other. And if they're
> related incorrectly the resulting predicate combination will not be
> true even though each predicate in the combination is.
>
> ~v~~

Okay, but the probability that a fox is an animal is 100%, whereas the
probability that an animal is a fox is, say, 0.01%. Since fox(x) implies
animal(x), given the 100% inclusion, we can eliminate the bit for
"animal". This really becomes a statistical correlation issue, at this
point. How do we determine which value between 0 and 1 denotes the
correlation between two predicates? We gather data, I guess, and maybe
discover some logical or causal relationships in the process.

01oo
From: Ben newsam on
On Tue, 24 Apr 2007 11:31:02 -0700, Lester Zick
<dontbother(a)nowhere.net> wrote:

>On Tue, 24 Apr 2007 00:43:24 +0100, Ben newsam
><ben.newsam.remove.this(a)gmail.com> wrote:
>
>>On Mon, 23 Apr 2007 11:54:05 -0400, Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com>
>>wrote:
>>
>>>If you want to talk about the truth values of individual facts used in
>>>deduction, by all means, go for it.
>>
>>I would counsel you seriously not to attempt it, Lester will only
>>obfuscate the "discussion", and then will start to hurl personal
>>insults at you.
>
>Or you could bore us to death with the experimental confirmation of
>spatial dimentionality. Is there nothing you can contribute to the
>advancement of science besides gratuitous meretricious ad hominem
>attacks on moi?

You don't know what "meretricious" means, do you?
From: Lester Zick on
On Tue, 24 Apr 2007 09:27:05 -0400, Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com>
wrote:

>> We already know you think there are any number of points in the
>> interval 0-1 so apriori declarations do not erase that inconsistency
>> between different sets of assumptions.
>
>I'm trying to keep it simple, and just discuss the mechanics of the most
>basic kind of logic, where absolute "truth" exists. It doesn't, in real
>science.

I don't understand where you think absolute truth exists if not in
real science.

~v~~
From: Lester Zick on
On Tue, 24 Apr 2007 09:27:05 -0400, Tony Orlow <tony(a)lightlink.com>
wrote:

>> A few days ago you asked about what I mean by "mechanics" or an
>> "exhaustive mechanics" and this is what I mean. You're welcome to
>> assume one mechanism but then you have to show how that one mechanism
>> produces every other aspect of the "mechanics" involved.
>
>That's what I TRIED to do.

Yes but you didn't show how that was done. All you did was assume it
was done.

~v~~