From: george on

Ross A. Finlayson wrote:
> Hi,
>
> In doing only cursory research, I'm apparently not
> the first person to suggest a theory with no non-
> logical axiomatization,

Don't sell yourself short.

> For example, and I only yesterday saw this from searching for
> eliminable definitions, Owen Holden, with whom I agree,
> presented a similar notion years ago, "Set Theory Without
> Axioms."

This was grossly mis-titled. It had axioms all over the place.
Far worse, it claimed to be able to insist that xey was a wff,
and yex was a wff, but (xey & yex) was NOT a wff. The kinds of
things this proposed system would've had to do to actually SPECIFY
what was a wff and what wasn't would've wound up simply TRANSLATING
axioms into rules of a grammar. He was utterly without a clue.
Unfortunately he got engaged (in that thread) by several people who
wanted to flaunt how much they knew about Quine's NFU set theory
("New Foundations (with Urelements)") and wound up mapping OH's
completely indefensible "restrictions on what's a WFF" to Quine's
coherently defined "stratification". OH's thread thus wound up
lasting a lot longer than it needed to.

http://groups-beta.google.com/group/sci.math/browse_thread/thread/cb67edabc2fd84c8/

> Basically I've arrived at that there is one consistent,
> complete, and concrete theory.

In it, is the continuum hypothesis true or false? And
Is the powerset of the union of all the sets in it
in it, or not? Is it categorical or does it have differing
models? If so, do both of them occur in some larger model
of it? Or is it even meaningful to speak of this theory
as having models at all?

From: george on
george wrote:
> > If you start with the first-order ZF axioms,
> > you will get one theory if you close them under first-order
> > classical consequence and a DIFFERENT theory if you close
> > them intuitionistically.
> > But to say that the classical way "is" "ZF-provability",
> > while the intuitionistic way isn't, is discriminating
> > against yourself.
>


Babylonian wrote:
> Yes, and I did that intentionally because the possible
> models of the two theories are different enough

Oh, please!
The various classical models of ZF are all "differnt
enough" FROM EACH OTHER that nobody can
get AROUND to caring how they might
differ from the non-classical ones. As the loudest
initial three examples, SOME OF THEM ARE COUNTABLE
while others are not, SOME OF THEM OBEY THE
AXIOM OF CHOICE, while others do not, and among
those that do obey AC, SOME OF THEM SATISFY THE
CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, while others do not.

> (you know what I mean) that I didn't
> think anyone wants to call them "ZF-sets".

My rebuttal of that is simply that THERE IS NO SUCH
THING as "the ZF-sets", classically! Classical-first-
order-ZF's myriad Tarskian models are just TOO chaotically
heterogeneous! The ONLY things you can LEGITIMATELY refer
to as "the ZF-sets" are the sets that provably exist (in
ALL classical models) of ZF! And EVEN THOSE sets get
"realized" in completely DIFFERENT ways in DIFFERENT models
of ZF!

For example, ZF's axiom of infinity requires the
existence of a certain set that's closed under successor.
But in a different model, this is a DIFFERENT set!
ZF also requires that this set have a powerset, and
it is true of this set, in ALL models, that it is
uncountable (from the "intra"-viewpoint of the model).
In the countable model, however, It MUST (from the "extra"-
viewpoint) be countable.

My point is that having proved about a thing that it's a
ZF set, UNLESS IT'S FINITE, is NOT having proved enough about
it to identify "which set" it is. THAT is a matter of OPINION
that VARIES from model to model.

Now, whatEVER you think the class of provably-extant
ZF-sets may be, it is clearly a different class of sets
from the ones that provably exist from the same axioms
under intuitionistic logic, but I repeat, BEFORE we go
down that road, YOU OWE us some INTUITIONISTIC MODEL THEORY!
CFOPL has a completeness theorem (something is provable iff
it's true in ALL models), and that alone lends the notion of
"ZF-set" what LITTLE coherence it has. But saying about
a universe (like sets from ZF under intuitionistic logic)
that it is "too different" from the "usual" ZF sets is NOT
reasonable, because given any model of ZF, you can get another
universe of sets that's ALSO "too different" JUST BY GOING TO
ANOTHER MODEL, classically, under the SAME paradigm!

The class of finite sets that provably exist IS the same
under both logics.

From: Paul Holbach on
> Chris Menzel wrote:
> > Paul Holbach <paulholbachSPAMBAN(a)freenet.de> said:

> > [Quoting Priest:]
> > "For any claim of the form 'all sets are so and so' to have
> > determinate sense there must be a determinate
> > totality over which the
> > quantifier ranges."

> Well, if the idea of "determinate totality" of things of a
> certain sort
> is meant to imply that there is an *object* of some sort --- the
> "totality" --- in addition to the things in question, this is just a
> non-sequitur. All we need to make sense of quantification is for the
> things quantified over to exist. There doesn't need to be a further
> thing that contains them (though of course there does in our usual
> mathematical *models* of quantification, which are themselves set
> theoretic objects).

Priest replies as follows:

"The Domain Principle seems patent to me. It would seem to be an
obvious and brute semantic fact that whenever there are things of a
certain kind, there are a l l of those things. Yet the principle has
drawn flak from some commentators. [...] Cartwright rejects the Domain
Principle, which he calls 'All-in-One-Principle', for reasons that he
explains as follows:

'There would appear to be every reason to think ... [the
All-in-One-Principle] false. Consider what it implies: that we cannot
speak of the cookies in the jar unless they constitute a set; that we
cannot speak of the natural numbers unless there is a set of which they
are the members; that we cannot speak of all pure sets unless there is
a class having them as members. I do not mean to imply that there is no
set the members of which are the cookies in the jar, nor that the
natural numbers do not constitute a set, nor even that there is no
class comprising the pure sets. The point is rather that the needs of
quantification are already served by there being simply the cookies in
the jar, the natural numbers, the pure sets; no additional objects are
required.
It is one thing for there to b e certain objects; it is another for
there to be a s e t, or set-like object, of which those objects are the
members. [...]'

The passage is rhetorically persuasive, but it achieves this effect by
trading on a number of important confusions. The first is between
quantification and description. Cartwright says that the Domain
Principle entails that 'one cannot speak of the cookies in the jar
unless they constitute a set'. It does not. Speaking of the cookies in
the jar does not quantify over the cookies. It refers to them by means
of a definite description. (It is a plural description, but this does
not affect the matter.) Clearly, to speak of the so and so(s) requires
us to presuppose no more than the existence of the so and so(s). The
passage also holds up as implausible the thought that one can speak of
all (pure) sets without there being a set of (pure) sets. This i s a
consequence of the Domain Principle. But once one separates it from the
case of descriptions, its supposed implausibility is much harder to
see. [...]
For any claim of the form 'all sets are so and so' to have determinate
sense there must be a determinate totality over which the quantifier
ranges. It would clearly be wrong to suppose that this totality is a
set satisfying the axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, or of some
other theory of sets; but that there is a well-defined totality seems
to me undeniable. Moreover, it is clearly a totality that we can think
of as a single thing, since we can legitimately refer to it as that
totality: the totality of all sets.
The passage continues by saying that 'the needs of quantification are
already served by there being simply the cookies in the jar'. This
brings us to the second confusion in the passage. Loosely, it is a
confusion between sense and reference. Whar are 'the needs of
quantification'? First of all, the variable of the quantifier must have
values. These are the cookies in the jar themselves: cookie_1,
cookie_2, cookie_3, ... . This, indeed, has nothing to do with
totalities of any kind. The totality is presupposed as soon as we talk,
not of the possible references of the variables, but of the sense of
the sentence containing the quantifier. This is not determinate unless
the totality of the cookies is determinate. We can put the point in a
Quinean fashion. The ontological commitments of the sentence concerned,
the entities there must be for the sentence to be true, are precisely
cookie_1, cookie_2, cookie_3, ... . But it is not the ontological
commitment of the sentence that is at issue here; it is the sense of
the sentence; the determinacy of this does require there to be a
determinate totality of cookies.
Of course, if this totality is thought of as something independent of
the cookies, this may again sound implausible. If you are talking about
certain things, and if all existences are distinct, then invoking the
existence of another entity would seem de trop. This is the rhetorical
strategy employed in the last sentence quoted, 'It is one thing for
there to b e certain objects; it is another for there to be a s e t, or
set-like object, of which those objects are the members'. But the set
and its members are not distinct existences. There could be no set of
cookies if there were no cookies--and vice versa. These are no atomic,
independent, existences."

[Priest, Graham (2002). /Beyond the limits of thought/ (2nd ed.).
Oxford: Oxford University Press.(S. 280ff)]

"For every potential infinity there is a corresponding actual infinity.
Following Hallett let us call this the Domain Principle. I take it to
be a formulation of the Kantian insight that totalisation is
conceptually unavoidable, though stated in a much more satisfactory way
than Kant ever managed to achieve."

[Priest, Graham (2002). /Beyond the limits of thought/ (2nd ed.).
Oxford: Oxford University Press.(S. 124)]

Of course, what most critics generally denounce is Priest's background
philosophy, his dialetheism.
Neil Tennant, for example, writes:

"It is not enough to give an honorific title like 'The Domain
Principle' to a tendentious piece of naiveté. Right at the outset [of
'Beyond the limits of thought'] Priest announces that 'there is a
totality (of all things expressible, describable, etc.) and an
appropriate operation that generates an object that is both within and
without the totality. I will call these situations 'Closure' and
'Transcendence', respectively' (p. 4). It is at this very point that
the question of the existence of the totality should be raised.
The lessons of the various paradoxes are, surely, that

(1) some 'totalities' cannot exist--in particular nothing contains
everything:
(2) no language can express every possible proposition:
(3) no theory can contain every truth.

Nowhere does Priest give these non-dialetheic responses the attention
they deserve."

[Source:
http://people.cohums.ohio-state.edu/tennant9/tennant_pb1998.pdf]

Is Priest really that naive ...?

Regards
PH

From: Bhupinder Singh Anand on
On May 2, 4:34 pm, Paul Holbach wrote:

PH>> Is Priest really that naive ...? <<PH

Paul
===
Not necessarily. It may simply reflect the possibility that, first,
Priest's hereticism could be confined to reasoning within the ambit of
standard interpretations of classical theory; and, second, that such
interpretations are yet to definitively address the issue of whether
the terms 'non-algorithmic' and 'non-constructive' are to be treated as
synonymous.

As I argue elsewhere, Goedel's reasoning can be taken to establish that
we can constructively, and in an intuitionistically unobjectionable
manner, establish that an arithmetical relation R(n) holds for any
given natural number n, but that there is no algorithmic way of
verifying this assertion (in other words, any Turing machine that
computes R(x), treated as a Boolean function, will go into a
verifiable, non-terminating, loop for some natural number n).

On this view, the particular argument between Priest and Cartwright,
Tennant, et al, becomes vacuous; we simply define any predicate [P] of
a formal language L as well-defined if, and only if, given any element
s in a domain D over which the variables of the language are
well-defined under an interpretation M, there is always an effective
method for determining whether P(s) holds or not in M for the
interpreted predicate P.

(Note that, given an interpretation M of a formal theory L, we can
always - according to a reasonable reading of Priest - define the
domain D as consisting of all elements that satisfy the axioms of L
under any interpretation. The fact that some D-elements are dissimilar
may need qualification when defining satisfaction in M but, prima
facie, this should not lead to any irresolvable issues.)

The existence of functions in real and complex analysis that are
continuous, but not uniformly continuous, and of sequences that are
convergent, but not uniformly convergent, indicates that such a
definition of a well-defined predicate can be mathematically
constructive, and intuitionistically unobjectionable.

We can then define [P] as well-defining a mathematical object (i.e., a
syntactic totality), say {x: P(x)}, in M if, and only if, there is an
algorithm (effective uniform method) for identifying elements such that
P(x) holds in M.

In the absence of such an algorithm, we may still have that, for any s
in D, it is effectively decidable whether or not P(s) holds in M, but
we can no longer treat all such elements as a syntactic totality that
can be referred to within, or by, the language without inviting
inconsistency.

On this view, the 'Domain' referred to by Priest need not be a
syntactic totality in the sense of being a mathematical object as
defined above. However, it can still be referred to, albeit loosely, as
a semantic totality for expressive, and philosophical, purposes, so
long as we do not associate any algorithmic properties with it without
a formal proof.

Regards,

Bhup

From: Babylonian on

george wrote:
>
> Oh, please!

Since you have asked politely, I'll give you a cookie at the end of my
post.

> Now, whatEVER you think the class of provably-extant
> ZF-sets may be, it is clearly a different class of sets
> from the ones that provably exist from the same axioms
> under intuitionistic logic, but I repeat, BEFORE we go
> down that road, YOU OWE us some INTUITIONISTIC MODEL THEORY!

Hint: it's model theory done intuitionistically.
I'll show you how.

> CFOPL has a completeness theorem (something is provable iff
> it's true in ALL models),

Intuitionist logic has the following theorem: pvq is provable if and
only if p is provable or q is provable. Remember this.

> But saying about
> a universe (like sets from ZF under intuitionistic logic)
> that it is "too different" from the "usual" ZF sets is NOT
> reasonable,

You may decide, when I give you the cookie I promised.

>
> The class of finite sets that provably exist IS the same
> under both logics.

Is that a constructive theorem, or a classical one?



Here is a classically finite set:

C={{}} if the CH is true
C={} if the CH is false.

I just want to know:

(i) does C exist in all models of the theory generated by intuitionist
logic? I say by the comprehension axiom it does.
(ii) is C={}v~C={} true in all said models? I say it isn't, because
CHv~CH is only provable if either CH or ~CH are provable, so there is a
model where C={}v~C={} is false. That is a model where CH is neither
true nor false, because ~(C={}v~C={}) is the statement that there can
never be a proof of C={}v~C={}.
(iii) Is the class of finite sets that provably exist the same under
both logics?

Use only inferences of intuitionist logic to justify your answers, or
you will convince me of nothing.

I see extensionality colluding with comprehension to give us:
(C={} == ~C={{}}) and (~C={} == C={{}}).
>From these, we obtain (C={}v~C={} == C={{}}v~C={{}})
or, if you like, (C={}vC={{}} == ~C={}v~C={{}})
Does this generate C={}v~C={}? Or C={}vC={{}}?
Remember, you can't generate CHv~CH until CH or ~CH are generated.


Enjoy your cookie.

First  |  Prev  |  Next  |  Last
Pages: 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16
Prev: What is wrong with this argument?
Next: Courage?